• Skip to primary navigation
  • Skip to main content
  • Skip to primary sidebar

Criminology Web logo

Beccaria – “On Crimes And Punishments”

November 4, 2018 By Margit

Cesare Beccaria is seen by many people as the “father of criminology.” Here is a brief summary of his ideas and famous essay “On Crimes and Punishments,” both in video and text format.

Table of Contents

Discussions about Crime and Punishment

Cesare Beccaria is seen by many people as the “father of criminology” for his ideas about crime, punishment, and criminal justice procedures. He was an Italian born as an aristocrat in the year 1738 in Milan. At that time European thought about crime and punishment was still very much dominated by the old idea that crime was sin and that it was caused by the devil and by demons. And in part to punish the devil and the demons that were causing crime, very harsh punishments were used. At the time when Beccaria came along, the era of Enlightenment was in full swing, and scientists were starting to challenge the old views, but the people who had political power were not ready to leave those old ideas behind yet.

Beccaria didn’t start out as an intellectual. In fact, he wasn’t considered to be above average or interested really when it came to science or philosophy. But after he completed his law studies at the University of Pavia, he started to surround himself with a group of young men who were interested in all kinds of philosophical issues and social problems. And the intellectual discussions that Beccaria was able to have with these people led him to question many of the practices that were common in his time, including the way in which offenders were being punished for their crimes.

Publication of Beccaria’s “On Crimes and Punishments”

Beccaria’s famous work, “On Crimes and Punishments,” was published in 1764, when he was 26 years old. His essay called out the barbaric and arbitrary ways in which the criminal justice system operated. Sentences were very harsh, torture was common, there was a lot of corruption, there were secret accusations and secret trials, and there was a lot of arbitrariness in the way in which sentences were imposed. There was no such thing as equality before the law. And powerful people of high status were treated very differently from people who were poor and who did not have a lot of status.

Beccaria’s ideas clashed dramatically with these practices. And I’ll go through some of the central principles that his work is based on.

Only the Law Can Prescribe Punishment

According to Beccaria, only the law can prescribe punishment. It is up to the legislator to define crime and to prescribe which punishment should be imposed. It is not up to a magistrate or a judge to impose a penalty if the legislator has not prescribed it. And neither is it up to a judge to change what the law says about how a crime should be punished. The judge should do exactly what the law says.

The Law Applies Equally to All People

In addition, Beccaria said that the law applies equally to all people. And so punishment should be the same for all people, regardless of their power and status.

Making the Law and Law Enforcement Public

Beccaria also believed in the power of making the law and law enforcement public. More specifically, laws should be published so that people actually know about them, and trials should be public, too. Only then can onlookers judge if the trial is fair.

According to Beccaria, the Law and Law Enforcement Should be Public

Beccaria: Punishments Should be Proportional, Certain, and Swift

Regarding severe punishment, Beccaria said that if severe punishments do not prevent crime, they should not be used. Instead, punishments should be proportional to the harm that the crime has caused. According to Beccaria, the aim of punishment is not to cause pain to the offender, but to prevent them from doing it again and to prevent other people from committing crime. In order to be able to do that, Beccaria believed that punishment should be certain and swift. He believed that if offenders were sure that they would be punished and if punishment would come as quickly as possible after the offense, that this would have the largest chance of preventing crime.

Beccaria Argued Against the Death Penalty

As another controversial issue, Beccaria argued against the death penalty. In his view, the state does not have the right to repay violence with more violence. And in addition to that, Beccaria believed that the death penalty was useless. The death penalty is momentary, it is not lasting and therefore the death penalty cannot be very successful in preventing crimes. Instead, lasting punishments, such as life imprisonment, would be more successful in preventing crimes, because potential offenders will find this a much more miserable condition than the death penalty.

Cesare Beccaria had radical ideas about crime and punishment for his time

No Right To Torture

Similarly, according to Cesare Beccaria, the state does not have the right to torture. Because no one is guilty until he or she is found guilty, no one has the right to punish a person by torturing him or her. Plus, people who are under torture will want the torture to stop and might therefore make false claims, including that they committed a crime they did not commit. So torture is also ineffective.

The Power of Education

Instead of torture and severe penalties, Beccaria believed that education is the most certain method of preventing crime.

Beccaria: Controversy and Success

Beccaria’s ideas are hardly controversial today, but they caused a lot of controversy at the time, because they were an attack on the entire criminal justice system. Beccaria initially published his essay anonymously, because he didn’t necessarily consider it to be a great idea to publish such radical ideas. And this idea was partly confirmed when the book was put on the black list of the Catholic Church for a full 200 years.

But even though his ideas were controversial back then, his essay became an immediate success. In fact, Cesare Beccaria’s ideas became the basis for all modern criminal justice systems and there is some evidence that his essay influenced the American and French revolutions which happened not long after the publication of the essay. His ideas were not original, because others had also proposed them, but Beccaria was the first one to present them in a consistent way. Many people were ready for the changes that he proposed, which is why his essay was such a success.

Beccaria ends his essay with what can be seen as a kind of summary of his view:

“So that any punishment be not an act of violence of one or of many against another, it is essential that it be public, prompt, necessary, minimal in severity as possible under given circumstances, proportional to the crime, and prescribed by the laws.”

You can find Cesare Beccaria’s full essay “On Crimes and Punishments” here .

Cesare Beccaria, father of criminology and classical criminology

essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

An Essay on Crimes and Punishments

  • Cesare Bonesana di Beccaria (author)
  • Voltaire (author)

An extremely influential Enlightenment treatise on legal reform in which Beccaria advocates the ending of torture and the death penalty. The book also contains a lengthy commentary by Voltaire which is an indication of high highly French enlightened thinkers regarded the work.

  • EBook PDF This text-based PDF or EBook was created from the HTML version of this book and is part of the Portable Library of Liberty.
  • ePub ePub standard file for your iPad or any e-reader compatible with that format
  • Facsimile PDF This is a facsimile or image-based PDF made from scans of the original book.
  • Kindle This is an E-book formatted for Amazon Kindle devices.

An Essay on Crimes and Punishments. By the Marquis Beccaria of Milan. With a Commentary by M. de Voltaire. A New Edition Corrected. (Albany: W.C. Little & Co., 1872).

The text is in the public domain.

  • United States

Related Collections:

essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

Detail from The Good Government (1338-9), by Ambrogio Lorenzetti. To the right: Magnanimity, Temperance and Justice seated above prisoners. From a fresco at the Palazzo Pubblico, Siena, Italy. Photo by Getty Images

The first socialist

Well before bentham, cesare beccaria radically questioned the right of the state to imprison and execute its citizens.

by Lorenzo Zucca   + BIO

On 12 April 1764, the citizens of Milan witnessed the brutal killing of Bartolomeo Luisetti. He had been condemned to death after being accused of sodomy. Luisetti was killed by asphyxiation and then burnt at the stake in front of the crowd. Throughout Europe, ruling elites believed that criminal justice had to be done and be seen to be done; and that criminal punishment had to be cruel so as to instil the fear of God in the people watching the horrific spectacle.

Cesare Beccaria witnessed the scene with horror. It was hard to believe that such cruelty could be regarded as a rational response. At the time of the event, Beccaria was only in his mid-20s, but already had strong political and philosophical views. Born in 1738, the first son of a prominent Milanese aristocrat, he was educated in a stifling Jesuit school in Parma. After studying law in Pavia, he returned to Milan where his eyes were opened by Montesquieu’s Lettres persanes (1721), or Persian Letters, an epistolary novel giving an outsider’s critical angle on Parisian customs. Beccaria entered the world of Enlightenment philosophy without hesitation; his lodestars were French and British intellectuals, and he was inspired in particular by reading Claude Adrien Helvétius, Denis Diderot, David Hume and John Locke.

In 1759, Beccaria became a member of the so-called ‘ academy of fisticuffs ’, a group of young Milanese aristocrats who rebelled against the oppression of the local elite, including their own families: the conflict was social and intergenerational. As they saw it, the interests of the few systematically trumped the interests of the many, and the laws were designed to increase the power of the privileged class. Their collaboration gave birth to a magazine called Il Caffé, a vehicle for reformist ideas. In 1762, Rousseau published The Social Contract, which provided Beccaria with an ideological framework: his treatise On Crimes and Punishments (1764) was published two years later, and 25 years before the French Revolution. Beccaria’s manifesto against cruel punishment spread swiftly through Europe, igniting radical reforms of repressive and coercive institutions throughout the continent.

Europe was at that time a profoundly hierarchical society, where a few privileged people ruled over the entire population with an arbitrary and unaccountable authority. Enlightenment philosophers took inequality to be the germ of social injustice. Beccaria had the ambition to radically reform his society, the institutions and the laws. It was an ambition shared by all Enlightenment thinkers in Europe, although the means to achieve that reform differed. France took the revolutionary path, while Milan engaged in steady reforms from within; Beccaria and the other pugilists were to play an important part in the administration of the city state.

European radical thinkers agreed that the Church was one of the strongest enforcers of inequality and subjection. Indeed, Italian political minds never ceased to be inspired by Niccolò Machiavelli’s central idea that Christian morality is incompatible with the morality of Civic Republicanism. The former is passive, and requires obedience to the established authority; the latter is active, and demands participation in the political affairs of the city. Only when the city was put first would institutions and laws reflect the interests of the whole society, and not just the vested interests of a few privileged ones.

Mindful of the interest of the many, Beccaria formulated a motto: la massima felicità divisa nel maggior numero (the greatest happiness shared among the greater number), which was subsequently adopted by the English utilitarian thinker Jeremy Bentham. Beccaria saw this maxim as a fundamental tenet of a new science, whose object was human society and whose name was ‘the science of man’, echoing Hume’s project in that phrase. Beccaria’s keen interest in mathematics and the sciences was channelled into the development of political economy and, soon afterwards, Beccaria was made chair of political economy in Milan, his first civic appointment.

Political economy for Beccaria was not just a tool with which to administer the state more efficiently; it was a Copernican revolution that explained the place of man in society, and the importance of reconceiving politics to serve the interests of any particular society. Political economy was intended to be the science of happiness, and aimed to replace religion as the guiding light of human behaviour. Beccaria was aware that great progress had been achieved in public matters through political economic reforms: trade replaced wars, print spread new ideas, and the relation between sovereign and subjects had been reconceived. But he also noted that little had been said and done about the cruelty and arbitrariness of criminal laws, the most immediate and visible display of brute force that had not yet been subject to rational analysis. He knew that it was not uncommon in those years to see people condemned to death and brutally ravaged in the public square with the intent of educating the citizenry.

On Crimes and Punishments was the first attempt to apply principles of political economy to the practice of punishment so as to humanise and rationalise the use of coercion by the state. After all, arbitrary and cruel punishment was the most immediate instrument that the state had to terrorise the people into submission, so as to avoid rebellion against the hierarchical structure of the society. The problem that Beccaria faced, then, was the simple fact that the elite had complete control of the law, which was a family business and a highly esoteric language that only the initiated could master. The path leading to the rational reform of penal law required a fundamental philosophical rethinking of the role and place of law in society.

B eccaria’s project was to dismantle the edifice of Roman law, which he mockingly referred to as ‘a few odd remnants of the laws of an ancient conquering race codified 1,200 years ago by a prince ruling at Constantinople’. The law was an arcane language of power, he felt; its content was unclear and imprecise as it was made of the odd admixture of Roman law, local customs, and it was ‘bundled up in the rambling volumes of obscure academic interpreters’. The opacity of the law was deliberate and instrumental to the control of the people.

Beccaria was a trained lawyer as well as a published mathematician, but philosophy was the key to his mission of reform. On Crimes and Punishments was the first glaring model of an excoriating work of censorial jurisprudence. As the English philosopher H L A Hart pointed out in 1982:

Bentham admired Beccaria not only because he agreed with his ideas and was stimulated by them but also because of Beccaria’s clear-headed conception of the kind of task on which he was engaged. According to Bentham, Beccaria was the first to embark on the criticism of law and the advocacy of reform without confusing this task with the description of the law that actually existed.

Beccaria’s work was entirely censorial; he was the first legal philosopher to maintain a very firm distinction between evaluation and description of the law.

Philosophy was the critical tool that Beccaria used to revolutionise the way in which European societies thought about the law. He was not interested in what the law said: the rule of law was, at the time of his writing, a chimera, since the law obeyed the rule of lawyers and catered for the interests of the few. Beccaria’s censorial approach focused on the law as a social institution that had always been taken for granted as a benevolent instrument of social order. Beccaria’s contribution to the philosophical methodology was monumental, but we should not forget that this philosophical turn had an underlying ambition of substantial social, political and institutional reform.

Beccaria was accused of being a ‘socialist’, in this term’s earliest known vernacular appearance. The charge came from two opposite directions: Padre Facchinei, a theologian who dreaded the rise of political economy as an immanent replacement for religion, used it first. Then came French economists, the so-called Physiocrats and other freemarketeers, who criticised Beccaria for the demanding role he gave the state in the economy, a stance that pointed the way to redistribution and social justice. Both Facchinei and the Physiocrats, along with Adam Smith, believed that the market was a spontaneous order guided by an invisible hand , possibly that of God. Beccaria disagreed: political institutions had a significant interventionist role to play in bridging the gap between the rich and the poor, which he plausibly regarded as the prime cause of crime.

Whether or not Beccaria was a socialist in a way we would recognise today is debatable. He certainly was, however, a secular political thinker whose main aim was to promote a free and equal society, and his main focus was on political justice as opposed to divine justice. Political justice, he believed, exists only because of the creation of a political society, which is a free association of men through the social contract. Thus, crime is defined as a breach of the social contract and not as a sin.

His originality lies in the way he arrives at a compromise between freedom and utility in the name of justice

Under the social contract, people agree to pool together a minimum portion of their freedom so as to guarantee its protection under the unified power of an authority: they swap their natural freedom in the state of nature for political freedom in the civil order of the state. The social contract is not a moment of celebration. People grudgingly agree to sign a pact with each other, and they are frequently tempted to break that pact to pursue their own advantage. What moves them to stick to the pact is the feeling of uncertainty, which makes it impossible to enjoy their natural freedom to act according to their immediate passions. The uncertainty as to how to exercise natural freedom leads everyone to accept a basic necessity: something has to be given away in order for everyone to enjoy genuine political freedom. Everyone’s minimum portion of natural freedom constitutes the public deposit of sovereignty which is the basis for the right to punish those actions that are injurious to the human society. The right to punish is a necessary evil that is exercised by the sovereign in order to respond to the radical uncertainty created by the unfettered exercise of natural freedom.

Political freedom is a psychological, qualitative state and not something that can be measured or quantified by the law. However, the law can help by giving clear and predictable guidance as to what counts as socially harmful behaviour, which will in turn result in the feeling of security. Criminal law’s aim is to guarantee political freedom. Beccaria’s insistence on the rule of law as the guarantor of individual liberty was later on enshrined in Article 4 of the French Declaration of the Rights of the Man and the Citizen (1789):

Liberty consists in the freedom to do everything which injures no one else; hence the exercise of the natural rights of each man has no limits except those which assure to the other members of the society the enjoyment of the same rights. These limits can only be determined by law.

Yet Beccaria’s originality does not lie in developing innovative interpretations of utility, political freedom or the social contract. His originality lies in the way he combines them to arrive at a compromise between freedom and utility in the name of justice. As far as criminal justice is concerned, the right to punish must be as narrow as possible if it is to be considered legitimate. The conclusion of On Crimes and Punishments could not be clearer:

In order that punishment should not be an act of violence perpetrated by one or many upon a private citizen, it is essential that it should be public, speedy, necessary, the minimum possible in the given circumstances, and determined by the law.

This theorem set in motion a cultural revolution. Beccaria’s little tract is the symbol of a philosophical movement that was bent on replacing entrenched forms of knowledge that were used by elites to preserve their privileges. The traditional understanding of the law was arcane and inaccessible. Beccaria wanted to replace it with a demystified conception of the law as the product of social fact, whose sole source would be legislation. He also knew that religion was still a potent form of social control; for that reason, he enthusiastically embraced the turn to political economy as a source of knowledge that government could use to ground its policies on reason. It is important to stress, however, that his philosophical method was the driving force of his ideas. He used philosophy to undermine the grounds of ancient law, and to carve out an immanent domain of politics, free from traditionalist and moralist understandings of justice.

T o justify punishment using reason meant to reduce – even to minimise – the quantity and quality of violence within the society. Not only the violence attached to crimes, but also the violence entailed by the reaction to crimes by private parties and by public authorities. Beccaria’s goal was to regulate the right to punish, and eradicate from its practice all forms of vengeance and religious beliefs. This idea of rational punishment has its advocates and its detractors, of course. Advocates understand that cruel and arbitrary punishment does not build a robust sense of trust in the public authority; they also believe that punishment might be a necessary deterrent against the use of private and public violence, so they accept punishment as expressing society’s commitment against violence. On the other hand, detractors believe that rationalising punishment amounts to giving the state a more efficient instrument with which to control and discipline us. Both views are important, but for Beccaria the project of rationalising punishment had a deep reformist meaning. It meant moving from a society that wielded punishment as a weapon of mass control to a society in which punishment would only be the last resort, and proportional to the crime.

Minimum Criminal Law is an apt formula to describe Beccaria’s critique of the practice of punishment. It refers to the specific nature of Beccaria’s social contract, which stipulates only a minimum transfer of natural freedom. In return, the contract will justify only a minimum restriction on natural freedom and suffering. The principle of minimum evil is deduced from the sacrificial nature of the contract: the minimum transfer of natural freedom for the maximum gain of political freedom.

Because the intervention of criminal law is limited by necessity, the state can use criminal law only as a final resort. If there are other means to prevent crimes, they should be used. This part of Beccaria’s thought is often ignored by those who consider him the forefather of utilitarianism in England or the ancestor of law and economics in the United States. This is so because Beccaria asks for the least penal intervention, and for the maximum provision of social services as part of the same package. It is criminal law that must be kept to a minimum, not the state. Beccaria requires a robust intervention of the state to redress inequality and to prevent crimes by educating and assisting people, not by repressing them.

Should we invest in tracking petty thieves, or should the system focus its attention on grand-scale criminality?

Beccaria’s views conquered Europe’s enlightened circles. He was received in Paris as a hero by the philosophes : Diderot annotated his little tract, and Voltaire wrote a review claiming that the reform of criminal law along Beccaria’s ideas ought to become one of the centrepieces of the Enlightenment’s reforms. Thomas Jefferson, who resided at the time in Paris, read the book in Italian, and sent copious notes back to the American founding fathers. Catherine II of Russia even invited Beccaria to lead the drafting of the Russian penal code and the reform of criminal justice. Beccaria’s tract became so popular that in 1866 Fyodor Dostoyevsky borrowed its title for one of his major works. In less than a century, Europe had started to implement his ideas: torture began to disappear, and the death penalty was abolished in a growing number of states. To celebrate the 100th anniversary of On Crimes and Punishments , the Italian Parliament voted in 1865 to abolish the death penalty in the kingdom and to erect a statue of Beccaria in his native Milan.

Quietly ignored for a century or more, Beccaria’s little book is being rediscovered today. Why? I suspect that his radical, reformist spirit hits a deep chord with many people. Inequality is again on the rise. In most countries, criminalisation is also on the rise: criminal law attempts to micromanage the behaviour of the many, while giving a blank cheque to wealthy billionaires whose tax-dodging and exploitative behaviour go unpunished.

We have once more reached a point where we need to reconsider the whole system of criminal justice. It is not about tinkering with what we have; it is about reforming criminal law radically. What hurts our society more? Should we invest endless amounts of resources tracking petty thieves and minor infringements, or should the system focus its attention on grand-scale criminality?

Beccaria denounced the inequality between the ruling class and the masses: he insisted that disproportionate inequality is bound to increase the crime rate because of poverty and injustice. In turn, that predicament is likely to bring only more social conflict and less certainty about security in society. Penal practices are likely to worsen as a result of this; and criminal law might well become once more a force serving the strong against the most vulnerable. In our societies, which are deeply polarised and unequal, Beccaria’s thought still rings true: we need more social justice and less criminal punishment. To have seen this already in the 18th century was remarkable.

Handwritten notes in black ink on an open notebook, with red and black corrections.

Thinkers and theories

Paper trails

Husserl’s well-tended archive has given him a rich afterlife, while Nietzsche’s was distorted by his axe-grinding sister

Peter Salmon

Medieval manuscript illustration of a goat and a person holding a disc, with gold circles in the background, surrounded by text in Latin script.

Philosophy of mind

The problem of erring animals

Three medieval thinkers struggled to explain how animals could make mistakes – and uncovered the nature of nonhuman minds

Elderly couple holding hands while standing in the street. The woman holds a colourful fan partially covering her face. A man in casual attire walks by on the right. Two trees and a white building with large windows are in the background, with three people looking out of one of the windows.

Moral progress is annoying

You might feel you can trust your gut to tell right from wrong, but the friction of social change shows that you can’t

Daniel Kelly & Evan Westra

Black and white photograph depicts a flood with rising water levels in a residential area. Strong currents and waves are visible, and houses in the background are partially submerged. Floodwater covers much of the landscape, with a lone tree and partial wooden structure in the foreground.

The disruption nexus

Moments of crisis, such as our own, are great opportunities for historic change, but only under highly specific conditions

Roman Krznaric

Close-up image of a jumping spider showing its detailed features, including multiple eyes, hairy legs, and fangs. The spider is facing forward with a white background.

What is intelligent life?

Our human minds hold us back from truly understanding the many brilliant ways that other creatures solve their problems

Abigail Desmond & Michael Haslam

A close-up of an orange and black butterfly perched on a leaf with a soft, pastel-coloured background.

History of ideas

Chaos and cause

Can a butterfly’s wings trigger a distant hurricane? The answer depends on the perspective you take: physics or human agency

Erik Van Aken

An Essay on Crimes and Punishments

Anonymous 1767 English translation of Dei delitti e delle pene (1764). Foundational text of modern criminology. Famous for the Marquis Beccaria's arguments against torture and capital punishment. Warning: template has been deprecated.

PUNISHMENTS,

TRANSLATED FROM THE ITALIAN;

COMMENTARY,

ATTRIBUTED TO

Mons. De VOLTAIRE,

TRANSLATED FROM THE FRENCH.

THE FOURTH EDITION

Printed for F. Newbery, at the Corner of St. Paul's Church-Yard.

  • Preface of the Translator
TABLE OF CONTENTS.
Page
Original:

worldwide because the author died at least 100 years ago.

Public domainfalsefalse

Translation:

worldwide because the author died at least 100 years ago.

Public domainfalsefalse

essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

  • Criminology
  • Works originally in Italian
  • Pages using center block with max-width parameter
  • Pages containing deprecated templates/Wikipediaref
  • Translations without translator information specified
  • Headers applying DefaultSort key

Navigation menu

Home

Search Google Appliance

  • Online Book Collections
  • Online Books by Topic
  • Biodiversity Heritage Library
  • Library Catalog (SIRIS)
  • Image Gallery
  • Art & Artist Files
  • Caldwell Lighting
  • Trade Literature
  • All Digital Collections
  • Current Exhibitions
  • Online Exhibitions
  • Past Exhibitions
  • Index of Library & Archival Exhibitions on the Web
  • Research Tools and OneSearch
  • E-journals, E-books, and Databases
  • Smithsonian Research Online (SRO)
  • Borrowing and Access Privileges
  • Smithsonian Libraries and Archives on PRISM (SI staff)
  • E-news Sign Up
  • Internships and Fellowships
  • Work with Us
  • About the Libraries
  • Library Locations
  • Departments
  • History of the Libraries
  • Advisory Board
  • Annual Reports
  • Adopt-a-Book
  • Ways to Give
  • Gifts-in-Kind

You are here

An essay on crimes and punishments.

APA Citation Beccaria, Cesare, marchese di. (1778). An essay on crimes and punishments. Printed for Alexander Donaldson, and sold at his shops in London and Edinburgh. Retrieved from https://doi.org/10.5479/sil.36417.39088001520584

MLA Citation Beccaria, Cesare, marchese di. An essay on crimes and punishments. A new edition corrected., Printed for Alexander Donaldson, and sold at his shops in London and Edinburgh, 1778, https://doi.org/10.5479/sil.36417.39088001520584

Chicago Beccaria, Cesare, marchese di. An essay on crimes and punishments. Printed for Alexander Donaldson, and sold at his shops in London and Edinburgh, 1778. doi: https://doi.org/10.5479/sil.36417.39088001520584

More Like This

Cover of The constitution, by-laws and house rules of the Westmoreland Club of Richmond, Va

Explore the Constitution

The constitution.

  • Read the Full Text

Dive Deeper

Constitution 101 course.

  • The Drafting Table
  • Supreme Court Cases Library
  • Founders' Library
  • Constitutional Rights: Origins & Travels

National Constitution Center Building

Start your constitutional learning journey

  • News & Debate Overview
  • Constitution Daily Blog
  • America's Town Hall Programs
  • Special Projects
  • Media Library

America’s Town Hall

America’s Town Hall

Watch videos of recent programs.

  • Education Overview

Constitution 101 Curriculum

  • Classroom Resources by Topic
  • Classroom Resources Library
  • Live Online Events
  • Professional Learning Opportunities
  • Constitution Day Resources

Student Watching Online Class

Explore our new 15-unit high school curriculum.

  • Explore the Museum
  • Plan Your Visit
  • Exhibits & Programs
  • Field Trips & Group Visits
  • Host Your Event
  • Buy Tickets

First Amendment Exhibit Historic Graphic

New exhibit

The first amendment, historic document, on crimes and punishments (1764).

Cesare Bonesana di Beccaria | 1764

Graphite underdrawing of Cesare Bonesana, Marchese di Beccaria, full-body portrait seated at table.

Cesare Bonesana di Beccaria, marquis of Gualdasco and Villaregio (1738-94), was the author of On Crimes and Punishments (1764). Inspired by the discussion of criminal law in Montesquieu’s Spirit of the Laws , this Milanese wrote a systematic treatise on the subject that was almost immediately translated into English and French. In it, he argued that the sole purpose of punishment is deterrence, and he denounced torture, the entertainment of secret accusations, and the death penalty; suggested that pre-trial detention can rarely be justified; and called for promptitude in punishment. The impact of his little book on the post-revolutionary revisal of the laws in the various nascent American states was considerable.

Selected by

Paul Rahe

Professor of History and Charles O. Lee and Louise K. Lee Chair in the Western Heritage at Hillsdale College

Jeffrey Rosen

Jeffrey Rosen

President and CEO, National Constitution Center

Colleen A. Sheehan

Colleen A. Sheehan

Professor of Politics at the Arizona State University School of Civic and Economic Thought and Leadership

Chapter 1: Of the Origin of Punishment

Laws are the conditions under which men, naturally independent, united themselves in society. Weary of living in a continual state of war, and of enjoying a liberty which became of little value, from the uncertainty of its duration, they sacrificed one part of it to enjoy the rest in peace and security. . . .

Chapter 2: Of the Right to Punish

Every punishment which does not arise from absolute necessity, says the great Montesquieu, is tyrannical. A proposition which may be made more general, thus. Every act of authority of one man over another, for which there is not an absolute necessity, is tyrannical. It is upon this, then, that the sovereign’s right to punish crimes is founded; that is, upon the necessity of defending the public liberty, intrusted to his care, from the usurpation of individuals. . . .

No man ever gave up his liberty merely for the good of the public. Such a chimera exists only in romances. Every individual wishes, if possible, to be exempt from the compacts that bind the rest of mankind. . . .

Observe, that by justice I understand nothing more than that bond, which is necessary to keep the interest of individuals united; without which, men would return to the original state of barbarity. All punishments, which exceed the necessity of preserving this bond, are in their nature unjust.

Chapter 6: Of the Proportion between Crimes and Punishments

It is not only the common interest of mankind that crimes should not be committed, but that crimes of every kind should be less frequent, in proportion to the evil they produce to society. Therefore, the means made use of by the legislature to prevent crimes, should be more powerful, in proportion as they are destructive of the public safety and happiness, and as the inducements to commit them are stronger. Therefore there ought to be a fixed proportion between crimes and punishments.

Chapter 12: Of the Intent of Punishments

From the foregoing considerations it is evident, that the intent of punishments is not to torment a sensible being, nor to undo a crime already committed. Is it possible that torments, and useless cruelty, the instruments of furious fanaticism, or of impotency of tyrants, can be authorized by a political body? which, so far from being influenced by passion, should be the cool moderator of the passions of individuals. Can the groans of a tortured wretch recal the time past, or reverse the crime he has committed? The end of punishment, therefore, is no other, than to prevent others from committing the like offence. Such punishments, therefore, and such a mode of inflicting them, ought to be chosen, as will make strongest and most lasting impressions on the minds of others, with the least torment to the body of the criminal.

Explore the full document

Modal title.

Modal body text goes here.

Share with Students

Cesare Beccaria

Of Crimes and Punishments

Cesare Bonesana, Marchese Beccaria, 1738-1794

Originally published in Italian in 1764

Introductory Material

Table of Contents

Dei delitti e delle pene. English: An essay on crimes and punishments. Written by the Marquis Beccaria, of Milan. With a commentary attributed to Monsieur de Voltaire. Philadelphia: Printed and sold by R. Bell, next door to St. Paul's Church, in Third-Street. MDCCLXXVIII. [1778]
Translated from the French by Edward D. Ingraham. Second American edition. Philadelphia (No. 175, Chesnut St.): Published by Philip H. Nicklin: A. Walker, printer, 24, Arch St., 1819.
 »  |
Original URL:
Maintained:
Original date: 1997/9/3 — 
-->
Test King Website is a great way to prepare you perfectly and effectively for real exam. Certification dumps from PassForSure can help you much better for final exam. Computer based training online and updated PassForSure mp3 guide can help you much better than any other online exam preparation sources. Testking exam engine is the handiest product for all those people who want to get brilliant success in actual exam. All the candidates can easily get through final exam with latest and updated audio lectures provided by . study guide, training solutions and study package are quite popular among the students. You are certain to pass with exam questions and dumps in first attempt. --> -->
-->
-->
-->

essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

Encyclopedia Britannica

  • Games & Quizzes
  • History & Society
  • Science & Tech
  • Biographies
  • Animals & Nature
  • Geography & Travel
  • Arts & Culture
  • On This Day
  • One Good Fact
  • New Articles
  • Lifestyles & Social Issues
  • Philosophy & Religion
  • Politics, Law & Government
  • World History
  • Health & Medicine
  • Browse Biographies
  • Birds, Reptiles & Other Vertebrates
  • Bugs, Mollusks & Other Invertebrates
  • Environment
  • Fossils & Geologic Time
  • Entertainment & Pop Culture
  • Sports & Recreation
  • Visual Arts
  • Demystified
  • Image Galleries
  • Infographics
  • Top Questions
  • Britannica Kids
  • Saving Earth
  • Space Next 50
  • Student Center

Start of Men's 100 meter sprint where Usain Bolt wins and sets a new world record at the 2008 Summer Olympic Games August 18, 2008 in Beijing, China.

An Essay On Crimes and Punishment

Learn about this topic in these articles:, contribution to penology.

…of Cesare Beccaria’s pamphlet on Crimes and Punishments in 1764. This represented a school of doctrine, born of the new humanitarian impulse of the 18th century, with which Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Voltaire, and Montesquieu in France and Jeremy Bentham in England were associated. This, which came afterwards to be known as…

discussed in biography

Cesare Beccaria

Farrer, Crimes and Punishment , 1880) was a celebrated volume on the reform of criminal justice.

place in Italian literature

Gabriele D'Annunzio

…delitti e delle pene (1764; On Crimes and Punishments ) made an eloquent plea for the abolition of torture and the death penalty.

reform movement in Lombardy

Italy

…delitti e delle pene (1764; An Essay On Crimes and Punishments ), castigated torture and capital punishment as symptoms of the injustice and inequality inherent in the society of the old regime.

On Crime and Punishments by Cesare Beccaria

This essay about Cesare Beccaria’s “On Crimes and Punishments” examines the significant impact of the 1764 treatise on the development of modern legal systems. Beccaria’s work was groundbreaking in advocating for the principles of just punishment, deterrence over retribution, and the abolition of capital punishment. He argued that punishment should be prompt, certain, and proportional to the crime to effectively deter criminal activity. The essay highlights Beccaria’s ideas on the rationality of punishment, the ineffectiveness of torture and death penalties, and the importance of proportionality in sentencing. These concepts have profoundly influenced modern criminal law, leading to reforms that emphasize humane and rational responses to crime. Beccaria’s advocacy for prevention through clear laws and public education is also discussed as foundational to contemporary approaches in criminology and legal education, showing his lasting influence on constitutional law in the United States and legal reforms across Europe.

How it works

Cesare Beccaria’s “On Crimes and Punishments” stands as a seminal opus in the annals of legal philosophy and criminology, initially published in 1764. This treatise marked one of the inaugural endeavors at meticulously scrutinizing law and the justice apparatus, championing reforms that would subsequently impact significant legal frameworks across Europe and America. This exposition delves into the pivotal motifs of Beccaria’s oeuvre, its historical milieu, and its enduring ramifications on contemporary legal methodologies and theories of punitive measures.

Beccaria penned “On Crimes and Punishments” in reaction to his observations of the inequity and barbarity inherent in the criminal justice systems of the 18th century.

During that epoch, legal frameworks were capricious, merciless, and disproportionately draconian. Penalties frequently encompassed torment and executions, typically enacted in public displays. Beccaria repudiated these methodologies on philosophical, fiscal, and humanitarian grounds, positing a legal structure that was coherent, equitable, and commensurate to the transgressions perpetrated.

A pivotal contention of Beccaria’s treatise is that the objective of punitive measures should be deterrence, rather than retribution. This constituted a paradigmatic deviation from the prevailing ideologies of the era, which construed punitive measures as a manifestation of retributive justice meted out by divine prerogative. Beccaria contended that for punitive measures to be efficacious, they must be expeditious and unequivocal, informing prospective malefactors of the repercussions should they engage in transgressions. This precept influenced the evolution of the classical school of criminology, which accentuates the import of rationality and deterrence.

Beccaria also introduced the notion that capital punishment is neither a efficacious nor a requisite mode of penalization. He contended that it was not efficacious in dissuading transgressions more than life incarceration and that it constituted an irrevocable act of aggression by the state that could culminate in judicial fallacies proving fatal. This constituted a revolutionary notion that instigated the movement toward the abolition of capital punishment in sundry nations.

Another momentous contribution of Beccaria’s opus is his advocacy for the commensurability between transgressions and punitive measures. He opined that the severity of the penalty should commensurate with the gravity of the transgression to uphold societal order and discourage further transgressions. This principle has evolved into a cornerstone of contemporary legal frameworks globally, influencing both the formulation of penalties and the dispensation of justice.

“On Crimes and Punishments” also deliberates on the significance of precluding transgressions rather than penalizing them. Beccaria champions a regimen of laws to guarantee lucid definitions of transgressions and the corresponding punitive measures, contending that this lucidity would aid in deterring transgressions in the first place. He also underscores the role of education in transgression prevention, suggesting that an enlightened populace is less inclined to engage in transgressions.

The impact of Beccaria’s opus transcends his immediate epoch. “On Crimes and Punishments” galvanized and enlightened the framers of the U.S. Constitution and wielded a profound influence on the evolution of the American criminal justice apparatus. His ideologies also informed legal reforms in his native Italy and throughout Europe, laying the groundwork for modern criminal jurisprudence and the eradication of torture and capital punishment in myriad regions of the globe.

In summation, Cesare Beccaria’s “On Crimes and Punishments” is a pivotal oeuvre that persists in resonating across the realms of law, criminal justice, and human rights. Its advocacy for humane and reasoned approaches to punitive measures has molded the foundational precepts of contemporary legal frameworks, rendering it one of the most seminal works in the annals of criminal jurisprudence and justice.

owl

Cite this page

On Crime And Punishments By Cesare Beccaria. (2024, Apr 22). Retrieved from https://papersowl.com/examples/on-crime-and-punishments-by-cesare-beccaria/

"On Crime And Punishments By Cesare Beccaria." PapersOwl.com , 22 Apr 2024, https://papersowl.com/examples/on-crime-and-punishments-by-cesare-beccaria/

PapersOwl.com. (2024). On Crime And Punishments By Cesare Beccaria . [Online]. Available at: https://papersowl.com/examples/on-crime-and-punishments-by-cesare-beccaria/ [Accessed: 29 Jun. 2024]

"On Crime And Punishments By Cesare Beccaria." PapersOwl.com, Apr 22, 2024. Accessed June 29, 2024. https://papersowl.com/examples/on-crime-and-punishments-by-cesare-beccaria/

"On Crime And Punishments By Cesare Beccaria," PapersOwl.com , 22-Apr-2024. [Online]. Available: https://papersowl.com/examples/on-crime-and-punishments-by-cesare-beccaria/. [Accessed: 29-Jun-2024]

PapersOwl.com. (2024). On Crime And Punishments By Cesare Beccaria . [Online]. Available at: https://papersowl.com/examples/on-crime-and-punishments-by-cesare-beccaria/ [Accessed: 29-Jun-2024]

Don't let plagiarism ruin your grade

Hire a writer to get a unique paper crafted to your needs.

owl

Our writers will help you fix any mistakes and get an A+!

Please check your inbox.

You can order an original essay written according to your instructions.

Trusted by over 1 million students worldwide

1. Tell Us Your Requirements

2. Pick your perfect writer

3. Get Your Paper and Pay

Hi! I'm Amy, your personal assistant!

Don't know where to start? Give me your paper requirements and I connect you to an academic expert.

short deadlines

100% Plagiarism-Free

Certified writers

The Online Books Page

An essay on crimes and punishments.

:An essay on crimes and punishments
:
:
Printed for J. Almon, opposite Burlington-House, Piccadilly, 1767
  
This is an uncurated book entry from our extended bookshelves, readable online now but without a stable link here. You should not bookmark this page, but you can to our curated collection, which has stable links.
  
Look for editions of this book at , or .

Help with reading books -- Report a bad link -- Suggest a new listing

Home -- Search -- New Listings -- Authors -- Titles -- Subjects -- Serials

Books -- News -- Features -- Archives -- The Inside Story

Edited by John Mark Ockerbloom (onlinebooks@pobox.upenn.edu) OBP copyrights and licenses .

The Atlas Society Logo

Join Our Newsletter!

Beccaria Thou Shouldst Be Alive in This Hour

Beccaria Thou Shouldst Be Alive in This Hour

essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

By Walter Donway

Some 250 years ago, he systemactically directed the spotlight of reason on Europe’s chaotic systems of policing, its arbitary and torture-driven judiciary, and nightmare prisons. His thinking profoundly shaped the new United States of America. It is a legacy that will not endure automatically and without a philosophical foundation. Beccaria’s story tells us why. 

The Age of Enlightenment (conventionally, 1685–1815) saw the nations of Europe refocus from religion to the human condition on earth, reason as the method of improving it, and the rights of the individual. But in what field did this new commitment have the most personal meaning for individual lives? Where, in modern parlance, did “the rubber hit the road”?

I vote confidently for a man who spent his life in Milan, Italy, often in the grip of depression, loath to leave his familiar surroundings. He became the first to apply reason to penology: the first to mount arguments against the death penalty, against torture to obtain confessions, against monstrously inhuman prison conditions, and against punishment as only vengeance instead of reform—to name a few issues.

Here were the Enlightenment’s rays falling upon some of the darkest regions of human life.

He is called the “father of criminal justice” and the “father of criminal law.” Here were the Enlightenment’s rays falling upon some of the darkest regions of human life. Among his accomplishments, he influenced—profoundly—the founders of the new American republic and the constitution they drafted.

My impression is that Cesare Bonesana di Beccaria , the Marquis of Gualdrasco and Villareggio, born in Milan in 1738 (fifteen years after Adam Smith’s birth in Scotland and twenty-five years after Denis Diderot’s in France), is not generally known in the United States today. Yet, as a criminologist, economist, philosopher, and office holder, he is held to be among the greatest thinkers of the Age of Enlightenment. He published the first full work on reform of the criminal justice system, including penology.

Beccaria attended a Jesuit College in the city of Parma, reportedly bored and rebellious against what he saw as dogma, but then went to the University of Pavia, where he took his degree in law. So typical of the brightest minds of the age, he excelled at mathematics, the prototypical expression of “reason” and rational system. But even that lost interest for him when he discovered the works of Baron de Montesquieu , the French judge, writer, and historian, and turned his mind to economics. (By then, works of genius of Enlightenment thinkers in many fields were available.)

Beccaria’s response to the medieval education still dominant at the time—a response we see in Adam Smith at Oxford—was a lack of interest in scholastics that bordered on lethargy. Then, in his mid-twenties, Beccaria befriended two brothers, Pietro and Alessandro Verri, and, with other young aristocrats in Milan, formed a literary society (in Italy typically called an “academy” and frequently, as elsewhere, a locus of intellectual ferment). They named it the “Academy of the Fist” to poke fun at sometimes pretentious academies popping up around Italy, and they adopted as a prime topic reforming the criminal justice system. In its pursuit, members read Enlightenment figures such as Helvetius, Diderot, Hume, and Montesquieu.

Four years out of law school, and bumped into motion by members of the group, Beccaria wrote a tract (pamphlet) taking on the chaotic currency of the Milanese states and pointing to a reform. It is of purely historical interest, today, but did reveal a writer capable of force and clarity. But by then, he had found his subject, and, again, the Academy of the Fist, with sessions held at the Verri home, was the inspiration and catalyst.

Torture Ingenious and Horrible

To set the context of Beccaria’s career, it is worth quoting at length a chapter from Prof. Elio Monachesi’s essay “Pioneers in Criminology IX—Cesare Beccaria,” from the Journal of Criminology and Law :

Criminal law of eighteenth-century Europe vested in public officials the power to deprive persons of their freedom, property and life without regard for any of the principles which are now embodied in the phrase “due process of law.” Secret accusations were in vogue and persons were imprisoned on the flimsiest of evidence.

Torture, ingenious and horrible, was employed to wrench confessions from the recalcitrant. Judges were permitted to exercise unlimited discretion in punishing those convicted of crime. The sentences imposed were arbitrary, inconsistent, and depended upon the status and power of the convicted. Punishments inflicted upon the more unfortunate of the offenders were extremely severe. A great array of crimes was punished by death not infrequently preceded by inhuman atrocities. Equality before the law as a principle of justice was practically non-existent, but rather the treatment accorded persons depended solely upon the station in life of the offender. In practice, no distinction was made between the accused and the convicted. Both were detained in the same institution and subjected to the same horrors of incarceration. This same practice prevailed in regard to the convicted young and old, the murderer and the bankrupt, first offenders and hardened criminals, men and women. All . . . were promiscuously thrown together free to intermingle and interact. 

Small wonder Enlightenment Europe, and America, would greet Beccaria’s work with sustained applause.

Both Pietro, then writing a history of torture, and Alessandro, a prison official in Milan, encouraged Beccaria to write his book An Essay on Crimes and Punishments ( Del delitti e delle pene ), the work above all for which he is remembered. The Verri brothers could supply first-hand observations of the criminal justice system and hellish conditions in prisons. For ideas, Beccaria had the sounding board of his Academy friends.

Today, what Beccaria published in 1764 is viewed as the climax of the Enlightenment in Milan. In his treatise, he mounts some of the first arguments against the death penalty. On Crimes and Punishments is also the first extensive book on penology and reform of the criminal justice system. True to form for Enlightenment thinkers, Beccaria urged that criminal justice and reform conform to rational principles. To some extent, he built upon the theoretical, historical work of his models such as the Dutch scholar and jurist Hugo Grotius to fashion a powerful work of advocacy as well as theory. But Beccaria’s was a work of advocacy and a call to action.

“A Judge Is Required To Complete A Perfect Syllogism”

Here , Beccaria gives voice to a certain rationalistic Enlightenment mentality, writing: “For every crime that comes before him, a judge is required to complete a perfect syllogism in which the major premise must be the general law; the minor, the action that conforms or does not conform to the law; and the conclusion, acquittal or punishment. If the judge were constrained, or if he desired to frame even a single additional syllogism, the door would thereby be opened to uncertainty.”

How to enforce this constraint on judges? If laws are defined so clearly (today called a “bright line”) that the entire populace understands them, then the judge dare not weave a spell of words to conjure some other meaning.

The abuses he protests in this relatively short book are: torture to extract confessions , secret accusers, judges with unconstrained power, inconsistent sentencing influenced by personal connections or lack of them, and capital punishment, which was then used for even minor transgressions. He writes: “It seems so absurd to me that the laws, that are the expression of the public will, that hate and punish the murder, make one themselves, and, to dissuade citizens from the murder, order a public murder.”

Beccaria pays tribute to “the immortal Montesquieu” for inspiring humanism, then erects a position on the foundations of social contract theory (he credits Rousseau) and utility theory. Indeed, if social contract theory does not stand, then the structure of Beccaria’s argument wobbles. If it does stand as his “major premise,” then Beccaria is difficult to refute.

At the same time, however, he laid the foundations of a purely rationalistic approach to social change. All institutions and practices that do not fit your deductive system must be destroyed. It seemed to work well when applied to the field of criminal justice. But it is the premise, later applied to society as a whole, that Edmund Burke and others saw at work when “Paris went mad” during the French Revolution and which Burke challenged with his doctrine of conservatism.

Thus, for Beccaria, punishment is justified not as retaliation or personal vengeance but to uphold the social contract. Turning to utility, known then, but later inspired by Beccaria, far more extensively developed by Jeremy Bentham , founder of the school of Utilitarianism, Beccaria advocates methods of punishment that will promote the greatest public good or the amount of “happiness” in the world. “Just” punishment is defined, in effect, as practical punishment: “For a punishment to be just it should consist of only such gradations of intensity as suffice to deter men from committing crimes.”

In urging that punishment follow swiftly and consistently the commission of a crime, Beccaria invokes the Scottish philosopher David Hume ’s thoughts on induction as based upon the proximity of cause and effect. Temporal proximity of crime and punishment would associate them in the minds of potential or repeat criminals and achieve what we call deterrence. His famous statement: “Crimes are more effectually prevented by the certainty than the severity of punishment.”

His ideas—common knowledge, today—were new to most people, including the whole hierarchy of the police-judiciary-penal system. Beccaria’s book—again, typical of the Enlightenment—was translated posthaste into French and English, going through several editions. A side note, here, is that the French translator saw problems with the organization and clarity of the material and omitted, added, or moved around whole sections of the book as he saw fit. Beccaria did write a letter approving the changes, but scholars point out that the result was two quite different books.

On Dueling, Suicide, Bounties, and Bearing Arms

Proceeding on a view of human nature as defined by free will, potential rationality, and a mind manipulatable by psychology and social pressures, Beccaria addresses issues such as dueling (instead pass laws protecting individuals from insults to their honor), laws against suicide (ineffective), bounty hunting (shows government is weak), criminal law (clear definition of crimes to discourage interpretation by judges), punishments (commensurate with the crime, the worst being treason, which harms the social contract), gun control (not useful, disarms only those not disposed to commit a crime), and education (best long-term preventive measure against crime).

Thomas Jefferson, in his Legal Commonplace Book , 1762–1767, copied this passage on gun control: “The laws of this nature are those which forbid to wear [Jefferson would later write “bear”] arms, disarming those only who are not disposed to commit the crime which the laws mean to prevent.” And such law “certainly makes the situation of the assaulted worse, and of the assailants better, and rather encourages than prevents murder, as it requires less courage to attack unarmed than armed persons.”

Speaking of assaults, so potentially controversial were Beccaria’s views that he published his book anonymously. He was barely twenty-six years old. Only when praise came from around the world— Catherine the Great in Russia publicly endorsed it, Thomas Jefferson and John Adams quoted it, and Milan’s officials approved it—did the excessively shy Beccaria republish his book with his name on it.

The same shyness plagued his only trip abroad, when he was invited to Paris to meet other Enlightenment greats. The Verri brothers, as always, supported him and the philosophes welcomed him, but his shyness did not play well in Paris. He left soon, and by doing so, broke with the Verri brothers, baffled by his headlong retreat from success and celebrity, and went back to his young wife, Teresa, and his children, in Milan. He never again traveled outside Italy. One result was isolation from the friends whose inspiration and input had catalyzed and supported On Crimes and Punishments . Beccaria tried but never could complete another book. Still, his book’s celebrity bore him forward. Legal scholars hailed it, European emperors took the pledge, and reform of many European penal codes followed. The Grand Duchy of Tuscany became the first nation in the world to abolish the death penalty (accepting Beccaria’s argument from utility, but not that the state had no right to execute citizens). In the English-speaking world, apart from America, thinkers like Sir William Blackstone , the great English scholar of law, and Jeremy Bentham incorporated some of his ideas.

Beccaria received an appointment in 1768 to a chair of law and economy created for him at the Palatine University of Milan. His lectures on political economy place him in the English school of economists with their strict utilitarianism. Beccaria also entered government on the Milanese supreme economic council and a board commissioned to promote judicial reform. There, he managed to shine, at least occasionally, leading some important reforms not just in criminal justice and penology but also other government administration.

He died in Milan in 1794, in his mid-fifties. Even before he died, he had seen his work reflected in the rights enumerated in the U.S. Constitution and Bill of Rights .

His ideas never have become uncontroversial, of course, as easily seen in the ceaseless debates about the death penalty, gun control laws, and swift sentencing—to take but a few examples. But his impact on dispelling darkness from the lives of countless generations caught in the criminal justice system, and his gift of humanity to all of us, is an urgently needed reminder, in our time, of the reality of struggle and glory in the Age of Enlightenment.

This was originally published by The Online Library of Liberty on April 5, 2023.

Walter Donway’s new book is How Philosophers Changed Civilizations: The Age of Enlightenment (Romantic Revolution Books, 2023). He was a founding trustee of The Atlas Society.

"Walter's latest book is How Philosophers Change Civilizations: The Age of Enlightenment ."

essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

ATMs, Accessibility, and Human Needs

Ayn rand and film.

We’re fighting to restore access to 500,000+ books in court this week. Join us!

Internet Archive Audio

essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

  • This Just In
  • Grateful Dead
  • Old Time Radio
  • 78 RPMs and Cylinder Recordings
  • Audio Books & Poetry
  • Computers, Technology and Science
  • Music, Arts & Culture
  • News & Public Affairs
  • Spirituality & Religion
  • Radio News Archive

essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

  • Flickr Commons
  • Occupy Wall Street Flickr
  • NASA Images
  • Solar System Collection
  • Ames Research Center

essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

  • All Software
  • Old School Emulation
  • MS-DOS Games
  • Historical Software
  • Classic PC Games
  • Software Library
  • Kodi Archive and Support File
  • Vintage Software
  • CD-ROM Software
  • CD-ROM Software Library
  • Software Sites
  • Tucows Software Library
  • Shareware CD-ROMs
  • Software Capsules Compilation
  • CD-ROM Images
  • ZX Spectrum
  • DOOM Level CD

essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

  • Smithsonian Libraries
  • FEDLINK (US)
  • Lincoln Collection
  • American Libraries
  • Canadian Libraries
  • Universal Library
  • Project Gutenberg
  • Children's Library
  • Biodiversity Heritage Library
  • Books by Language
  • Additional Collections

essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

  • Prelinger Archives
  • Democracy Now!
  • Occupy Wall Street
  • TV NSA Clip Library
  • Animation & Cartoons
  • Arts & Music
  • Computers & Technology
  • Cultural & Academic Films
  • Ephemeral Films
  • Sports Videos
  • Videogame Videos
  • Youth Media

Search the history of over 866 billion web pages on the Internet.

Mobile Apps

  • Wayback Machine (iOS)
  • Wayback Machine (Android)

Browser Extensions

Archive-it subscription.

  • Explore the Collections
  • Build Collections

Save Page Now

Capture a web page as it appears now for use as a trusted citation in the future.

Please enter a valid web address

  • Donate Donate icon An illustration of a heart shape

An essay on crimes and punishments : translated from the Italian : with a commentary, attributed to Mons. de Voltaire, translated from the French

Bookreader item preview, share or embed this item, flag this item for.

  • Graphic Violence
  • Explicit Sexual Content
  • Hate Speech
  • Misinformation/Disinformation
  • Marketing/Phishing/Advertising
  • Misleading/Inaccurate/Missing Metadata

No copyright page found.

[WorldCat (this item)]

plus-circle Add Review comment Reviews

1,432 Views

4 Favorites

DOWNLOAD OPTIONS

For users with print-disabilities

IN COLLECTIONS

Uploaded by associate-nicholas-delancey on June 3, 2014

SIMILAR ITEMS (based on metadata)

IMAGES

  1. An Essay on Crimes and Punishments, With a Commentary by M de

    essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

  2. Beccaria Reading

    essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

  3. On Crimes and Punishment (Ockham Classics): Beccaria, Cesare

    essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

  4. On Crimes and Punishments

    essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

  5. An essay on crimes and punishments, translated from the Italian by

    essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

  6. An Essay on Crimes and Punishments: Translated from the Italian

    essay on crime and punishment by cesare beccaria

VIDEO

  1. CLASSICAL SCHOOL OF THOUGHT || THEORECTICAL PERSPECTIVES IN CRIMINOLOGY #criminology #css

  2. Si Cesare Beccaria, at ang kanyang kontribusyon sa lipunan

  3. OF THE RIGHT TO PUNISH

  4. is 300 words essay punishment enough for car accident #news #pune #puneaccident #facts

  5. Crime and Punishment by Fyodor Dostoyevsky

  6. The Purpose of Punishment: Deterrence and Incapacitation

COMMENTS

  1. PDF The Online Library of Liberty

    Cesare Bonesana di Beccaria, An Essay on Crimes and Punishments [1764] The Online Library Of Liberty This E-Book (PDF format) is published by Liberty Fund, Inc., a private, non-profit, educational foundation established in 1960 to encourage study of the ideal of a society of free and responsible individuals. 2010 was the 50th anniversary year of

  2. Beccaria

    Publication of Beccaria's "On Crimes and Punishments". Beccaria's famous work, "On Crimes and Punishments," was published in 1764, when he was 26 years old. His essay called out the barbaric and arbitrary ways in which the criminal justice system operated. Sentences were very harsh, torture was common, there was a lot of corruption ...

  3. An Essay on Crimes and Punishments

    An Essay on Crimes and Punishments. Cesare Bonesana di Beccaria (author) Voltaire (author) An extremely influential Enlightenment treatise on legal reform in which Beccaria advocates the ending of torture and the death penalty. The book also contains a lengthy commentary by Voltaire which is an indication of high highly French enlightened ...

  4. Cesare Beccaria's radical ideas on crime and punishment

    2,900 words. Syndicate this essay. On 12 April 1764, the citizens of Milan witnessed the brutal killing of Bartolomeo Luisetti. He had been condemned to death after being accused of sodomy. Luisetti was killed by asphyxiation and then burnt at the stake in front of the crowd. Throughout Europe, ruling elites believed that criminal justice had ...

  5. An essay on crimes and punishments : Beccaria, Cesare, marchese di

    An essay on crimes and punishments ... An essay on crimes and punishments by Beccaria, Cesare, marchese di, 1738-1794; Voltaire, 1694-1778. Publication date 1778 Topics Criminal law, Crime, Criminals, Punishment, Capital punishment, Torture, Law reform Publisher Edinburgh, Printed for Alexander Donaldson Collection smithsonian Contributor

  6. An essay on crimes and punishments : Beccaria, Cesare, marchese di

    An essay on crimes and punishments ... An essay on crimes and punishments by Beccaria, Cesare, marchese di, 1738-1794. ... Law reform, Capital punishment, Criminal Law, Crime, Punishment, Capital punishment, Crime, Criminal law, Criminals, Law reform, Punishment Publisher London : Printed for F. Newbery at the corner of St. Paul's Church-yard

  7. An Essay on Crimes and Punishments

    An Essay on Crimes and Punishments. information about this edition. sister projects: Wikidata item. Anonymous 1767 English translation of Dei delitti e delle pene (1764). Foundational text of modern criminology. Famous for the Marquis Beccaria's arguments against torture and capital punishment. Mons.

  8. An Essay on Crimes and Punishments : Voltaire, Cesare Beccaria : Free

    Book digitized by Google from the library of Oxford University and uploaded to the Internet Archive by user tpb.

  9. An essay on crimes and punishments

    Home » Books » An essay on crimes and punishments » An essay on crimes and punishments Beccaria, Cesare, marchese di ; Voltaire Printed for Alexander Donaldson, and sold at his shops in London and Edinburgh, 1778

  10. PDF 1. An Essay on Crimes and Punishments

    An Essay on Crimes and Punishments Cesare Beccaria Beccaria's book, An Essay on Crimes and Punishments, presents the first of the modern or scientific theories of crime. The book, first pub­ lished in 1764, became the foundation for the classical theory of criminology, which dominated

  11. On Crimes and Punishments (1764)

    Cesare Bonesana di Beccaria, marquis of Gualdasco and Villaregio (1738-94), was the author of On Crimes and Punishments (1764). Inspired by the discussion of criminal law in Montesquieu's Spirit of the Laws, this Milanese wrote a systematic treatise on the subject that was almost immediately translated into English and French.In it, he argued that the sole purpose of punishment is deterrence ...

  12. Cesare Beccaria: Of Crimes and Punishments

    Cesare Bonesana, Marchese Beccaria, 1738-1794. Originally published in Italian in 1764. Dei delitti e delle pene. English: An essay on crimes and punishments. Written by the Marquis Beccaria, of Milan. With a commentary attributed to Monsieur de Voltaire. Philadelphia: Printed and sold by R. Bell, next door to St. Paul's Church, in Third-Street.

  13. On Crimes and Punishments

    On Crimes and Punishments. Frontpage of the original Italian edition Dei delitti e delle pene. On Crimes and Punishments ( Italian: Dei delitti e delle pene [dei deˈlitti e ddelle ˈpeːne]) is a treatise written by Cesare Beccaria in 1764. The treatise condemned torture and the death penalty and was a founding work in the field of penology .

  14. An Essay On Crimes and Punishment

    Other articles where An Essay On Crimes and Punishment is discussed: penology: …of Cesare Beccaria's pamphlet on Crimes and Punishments in 1764. This represented a school of doctrine, born of the new humanitarian impulse of the 18th century, with which Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Voltaire, and Montesquieu in France and Jeremy Bentham in England were associated.

  15. An Essay on Crimes and Punishments

    Appears in 14 books from 1768-2004. Page 158 - To show mankind, that crimes are sometimes pardoned, and that punishment is not the necessary consequence, is to nourish the flattering hope of impunity, and is the cause of their considering every punishment inflicted as an act of injustice and oppression. Appears in 31 books from 1800-2004.

  16. On Crimes and Punishments by Cesare Beccaria

    Beccaria's On Crimes and Punishments. Cesare Beccaria's views on crime and punishment first took form with a close examination of the law and justice system. The Age of Enlightenment swept through ...

  17. Internet History Sourcebooks: Modern History

    Cesare Beccaria: Essay on Crimes and Punishments . ... The punishment of death is pernicious to society, from the example of barbarity it affords. If the passions, or the necessity of war, have taught men to shed the blood of their fellow creatures, the laws, which are intended to moderate the ferocity of mankind, should not increase it by ...

  18. On Crime and Punishments by Cesare Beccaria

    This essay about Cesare Beccaria's "On Crimes and Punishments" examines the significant impact of the 1764 treatise on the development of modern legal systems. Beccaria's work was groundbreaking in advocating for the principles of just punishment, deterrence over retribution, and the abolition of capital punishment.

  19. An Essay on Crimes and Punishments : Voltaire, Cesare Beccaria : Free

    Book digitized by Google from the library of the New York Public Library and uploaded to the Internet Archive by user tpb.

  20. An essay on crimes and punishments, by Cesare Beccaria et al.

    An essay on crimes and punishments: Author: Beccaria, Cesare, marchese di, 1738-1794: Author: Voltaire, 1694-1778: Note: Printed for J. Almon, opposite Burlington-House, Piccadilly, 1767 : Link: page images at HathiTrust: No stable link: This is an uncurated book entry from our extended bookshelves, readable online now but without a stable link ...

  21. Beccaria Thou Shouldst Be Alive in This Hour

    Here, Beccaria gives voice to a certain rationalistic Enlightenment mentality, writing: "For every crime that comes before him, a judge is required to complete a perfect syllogism in which the major premise must be the general law; the minor, the action that conforms or does not conform to the law; and the conclusion, acquittal or punishment ...

  22. An essay on crimes and punishments translated from the Italian of Cæsar

    An essay on crimes and punishments translated from the Italian of Cæsar Bonesana, marquis Beccaria by Beccaria, Cesare, marchese di, 1738-1794; Voltaire, 1694 ... Publication date 1819 Topics Crime, Capital punishment, Torture, Punishment, Law reform Publisher Philadelphia : Published by Philip H. Nicklin, No. 175, Chesnut St., A. Walker ...

  23. On Crime And Punishments By Cesare Beccaria

    He perceived a punishment should be: secure, swift and fittingly harsh. By Beccaria being interested in the prevention side of crime, his issue was to get rid of torture by having laws put down in writing and all offences and punishments. Free Essay: Cesare Beccaria was an Italian philosopher who lived throughout the 18th century (1738—1794).

  24. An essay on crimes and punishments : translated from the Italian : with

    Beccaria's very influential "Dei Delitti e delle Pene" was first published in Livorno in 1764, and the first English translation followed in 1767. Beccaria's book brought into the language the phrase "the greatest happiness of the greatest number" and his arguments about crime and punishment, revolutionary in their time, are part and parcel of ...