SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Autonomy in Moral and Political Philosophy

Individual autonomy is an idea that is generally understood to refer to the capacity to be one’s own person, to live one’s life according to reasons and motives that are taken as one’s own and not the product of manipulative or distorting external forces, to be in this way independent. It is a central value in the Kantian tradition of moral philosophy but it is also given fundamental status in John Stuart Mill’s version of utilitarian liberalism (Kant 1785/1983, Mill 1859/1975, ch. III). Examination of the concept of autonomy also figures centrally in debates over education policy, biomedical ethics, various legal freedoms and rights (such as freedom of speech and the right to privacy), as well as moral and political theory more broadly. In the realm of moral theory, seeing autonomy as a central value can be contrasted with alternative frameworks such an ethic of care, utilitarianism of some kinds, and an ethic of virtue. Autonomy has traditionally been thought to connote independence and hence to reflect assumptions of individualism in both moral thinking and designations of political status. For this reason, certain philosophical movements, such as certain strains of feminism, have resisted seeing autonomy as a value (Jaggar 1983, chap. 3). However, in recent decades, theorists have increasingly tried to structure the concept so as to sever its ties to this brand of individualism.

In all such discussions the concept of autonomy is the focus of much controversy and debate, disputes which focus attention on the fundamentals of moral and political philosophy and the Enlightenment conception of the person more generally.

1.1 Basic Distinctions

1.2 conceptual variations, 2.1 autonomy as an object of value, 2.2 autonomy and paternalism, 3.1 autonomy and the foundations of liberalism, 3.2 identity and conceptions of the self, 3.3 relational autonomy.

  • 3.4 Autonomy, Liberalism and Perfectionism

3.5 Autonomy and Political Liberalism

3.6 autonomy, justice and democracy, other internet resources, related entries, 1. the concept of autonomy.

In the western tradition, the view that individual autonomy is a basic moral and political value is very much a modern development. Putting moral weight on an individual’s ability to govern herself, independent of her place in a metaphysical order or her role in social structures and political institutions is very much the product of the modernist humanism of which much contemporary moral and political philosophy is an offshoot. (For historical discussions of autonomy, see Schneewind 1988, Swain 2016 and Rosich 2019). As such, it bears the weight of the controversies that this legacy has attracted. The idea that moral principles and obligations, as well as the legitimacy of political authority, should be grounded in the self-governing individual, considered apart from various contingencies of place, culture, and social relations, invites skeptics from several quarters. Autonomy, then, is very much at the vortex of the complex (re)consideration of modernity.

Put most simply, to be autonomous is to govern oneself, to be directed by considerations, desires, conditions, and characteristics that are not simply imposed externally upon one, but are part of what can somehow be considered one’s authentic self. Autonomy in this sense seems an irrefutable value, especially since its opposite — being guided by forces external to the self and which one cannot authentically embrace — seems to mark the height of oppression. But specifying more precisely the conditions of autonomy inevitably sparks controversy and invites skepticism about the claim that autonomy is an unqualified value for all people.

Autonomy plays various roles in theoretical accounts of persons, conceptions of moral obligation and responsibility, the justification of social policies and in numerous aspects of political theory. It forms the core of the Kantian conception of practical reason (see, e.g, Korsgaard 1996, Hill 1989) and, relatedly, connects to questions of moral responsibility (see Wolff 1970, 12–19). It is also seen as the aspect of persons that prevents or ought to prevent paternalistic interventions in their lives (Dworkin 1988, 121–29). It plays a role in education theory and policy, on some views specifying the core goal of liberal education generally (Gutmann 1987, Cuypers and Haji 2008; for discussion, see Brighouse 2000, 65–111). Also, despite many feminists’ reservations concerning the ideal of autonomy, it is sometimes seen as a valuable conceptual element in some feminist ideals, such as the identification and elimination of social conditions that victimize women and other (potentially) vulnerable people (Friedman 1997, Meyers 1987, Christman 1995. Veltman and Piper 2014)).

Several distinctions must be made to zero in on the kind of autonomy that is of greatest interest to moral and political theory. “Moral autonomy” refers to the capacity to impose the (putatively objective) moral law on oneself, and, following Kant, it is claimed as a fundamental organizing principle of all morality (Hill 1989). On the other hand, what can be called “personal autonomy” is meant as a trait that individuals can exhibit relative to any aspects of their lives, not limited to questions of moral obligation (Dworkin 1988, 34–47).

Personal (or individual) autonomy should also be distinguished from freedom , although again, there are many renderings of these concepts, and certainly some conceptions of positive freedom will be equivalent to what is often meant by autonomy (Berlin 1969, 131–34). Generally, one can distinguish autonomy from freedom in that the latter concerns the ability to act, without external or internal constraints and also (on some conceptions) with sufficient resources and power to make one’s desires effective (Berlin 1969, Crocker 1980, MacCallum 1967). Autonomy concerns the independence and authenticity of the desires (values, emotions, etc.) that move one to act in the first place. Some distinguish autonomy from freedom by insisting that freedom concerns particular acts while autonomy is a more global notion, referring to states of a person (Dworkin 1988, 13–15, 19–20). But autonomy can be used to refer both to the global condition (autonomous personhood) and as a more local notion (autonomous relative to a particular trait, motive, value, or social condition). Addicted smokers for example are autonomous persons in a general sense but (for some) helplessly unable to control their behavior regarding this one activity (Christman 1989, 13–14; cf. Meyers 1987, 66–67).

In addition, we must keep separate the idea of basic autonomy, the minimal status of being responsible, independent and able to speak for oneself, from ideal autonomy, an achievement that serves as a goal to which we might aspire and according to which a person is maximally authentic and free of manipulative, self-distorting influences. Any plausible conceptualization of basic autonomy must, among other things, imply that most adults who are not suffering from debilitating pathologies or are under oppressive and constricting conditions count as autonomous. Autonomy as an ideal, on the other hand, may well be enjoyed by very few if any individuals, for it functions as a goal to be attained.

The reason to construe basic autonomy broadly enough to include most adults is that autonomy connects with other status designators which apply (or, it is claimed, should apply) in this sweeping manner. Autonomy is connected, for example, to moral and legal responsibility, on some views (e.g., Ripstein 1999); autonomous agency is seen as necessary (and for some sufficient) for the condition of equal political standing; moreover, being autonomous stands as a barrier to unchecked paternalism, both in the personal, informal spheres and in legal arenas (Feinberg 1986). Lacking autonomy, as young children do, is a condition which allows or invites sympathy, care, paternalism and possibly pity. Therefore, a guiding consideration in evaluating particular conceptions of autonomy (though hardly a hard and fast test) will be whether it connects properly to these ancillary judgments (for discussion of “formal conditions” of a concept of autonomy, see Dworkin 1988, 7–10).

The variety of contexts in which the concept of autonomy functions has suggested to many that there are simply a number of different conceptions, and that the word simply refers to different elements in each of those contexts (Arpaly 2004). Others have claimed that while there may be a single over-arching concept of autonomy, we should think in terms of separable dimensions of it rather than an all or nothing idea (Mackenzei 2014 and Killmister 2017). Feinberg has claimed that there are at least four different meanings of “autonomy” in moral and political philosophy: the capacity to govern oneself, the actual condition of self-government, a personal ideal, and a set of rights expressive of one’s sovereignty over oneself (Feinberg 1989). One might argue that central to all of these uses is a conception of the person able to act, reflect, and choose on the basis of factors that are somehow her own (authentic in some sense). Nevertheless, it is clear that formulating a “theory” of the concept will involve more than merely uncovering the obscure details of the idea’s essence, for autonomy, like many concepts central to contentious moral or political debate is itself essentially contested. So a theory of autonomy is simply a conceptual model aimed at capturing the general sense of “self-rule” or “self-government” (ideas which obviously admit of their own vagaries) and which can be used to support principles or policies the theory attempts to justify.

The idea of self-rule contains two components: the independence of one’s deliberation and choice from manipulation by others, and the capacity to rule oneself (see Dworkin 1989, 61f and Arneson 1991). However, the ability to rule oneself will lie at the core of the concept, since a full account of that capability will surely entail the freedom from external manipulation characteristic of independence. Indeed, it could be claimed that independence per se has no fixed meaning or necessary connection with self-government unless we know what kinds of independence is required for self-rule (cf., however Raz 1986, 373–78).

Focusing, then, on the requirements of self rule, it can be claimed that to govern oneself one must be in a position to act competently based on desires (values, conditions, etc.) that are in some sense one’s own. This picks out the two families of conditions often proffered in conceptions of autonomy: competency conditions and authenticity conditions. Competency includes various capacities for rational thought, self-control, and freedom from debilitating pathologies, systematic self-deception, and so on. (Different accounts include different conditions: see, for example, Berofsky 1995, R. Young 1991, Haworth 1986, Meyers 1989.)

Authenticity conditions often include the capacity to reflect upon and endorse (or identify with) one’s desires, values, and so on. The most influential models of authenticity in this vein claim that autonomy requires second-order identification with first order desires. For Frankfurt, for instance, such second-order desires must actually have the structure of a volition: wanting that the first order desires issue in action, that they comprise one’s will. Moreover, such identification, on his view, must be “wholehearted” for the resulting action to count as free (autonomous). [ 1 ]

This overall approach to autonomy has been very influential, and several writers have developed variations of it and defended it against objections. The most prominent objections concern, on the one hand, the fatal ambiguities of the concept of “identification” and, on the other, the threat of an infinite regress of conditions. The first problem surrounds the different ways that one can be said to “identify” with a desire, each of which render the view conceptually suspect. Either one identifies with an aspect of oneself in the sense of simply acknowledging it (without judgment) or one identifies with a desire in an aspirational, approving sense of that term. In the first case, however, identification would clearly not be a consistent mark of autonomy, for one could easily identify as part of oneself any manner of addictive, constricting, or imposed aspects of one’s make-up. But approving of a trait is also problematic as a requirement of autonomy, for there are many perfectly authentic aspects of myself (ones for which I can and should be held fully responsible for example) which I do not fully approve of. I’m not perfect, but does that mean that I am thereby not autonomous? (Cf. Watson 1989, Berofsky 1995, 99–102). [ 2 ]

This model stresses internal self-reflection and procedural independence. However, the view includes no stipulations about the content of the desires, values, and so on, in virtue of which one is considered autonomous, specifically there is no requirement that one act from desires independently of others. Were there to be such a requirement, it would involve what is called “substantive independence”. Some writers have insisted that the autonomous person must enjoy substantive independence as well as procedural independence (e.g., Stoljar 2000, Benson 1987, 2005, Oshana 2006). The motivation for such a position is the idea a person under constrained life situations should not be considered autonomous no matter how “voluntary” (or autonomous) was the choice that put her in that position (cf. Meyers 2000). This claim, however, threatens to rob the attribution of autonomy of any claim to value neutrality it may otherwise carry, for if, conceptually, one is not autonomous when one (freely, rationally, without manipulation) chooses to enter conditions of severely limited choice, then the concept is reserved to only those lifestyles and value pursuits that are seen as acceptable from a particular political or theoretical point of view. I will return to this line of thought in a moment. In rejoinder, it has been claimed that such procedural neutrality could not capture the value autonomy has for people, and moreover, a “weakly substantive” view can be compatible with a political form of liberalism as long as the values inherent in the concept could be accepted by reasonable persons in an overlapping consensus (see Freyenhagen 2017).

One variation on the internal self-reflection model focuses on the importance of the personal history of the agent as an element of her autonomy (Christman 1991, Mele 1993; cf. Fisher & Ravizza 1998; cf. also Raz 1986, 371). On these views, the question of whether a person is autonomous at a time depends on the processes by which she came to be the way she is. It is not clear that such a focus will be able to avoid the problems raised about internal reflection models (see Mele 1991, Mackenzie & Stoljar 2000b, 16–17), but such a move attempts to embrace a conception of the self of self-government which is not only social but diachronically structured (see, e.g., Cuypers 2001).

For those who are wary of the postulate of reflective self endorsement, an alternative approach is to equate autonomy with simply a set of competences, such as the capacity to choose deliberatively, rationally, and, as Berofsky claims, “objectively” (see Berofsky 1995, Meyers 1989). This locates autonomy in the general capacity to respond to reasons, and not, for example, in acts of internal self-identification. However, even in these accounts, the capacity to think critically and reflectively is necessary for autonomy as one of the competences in question, even though the reflective thought required need not refer to external values or ideals (Berofsky 1995, ch. 5).

Further difficulties have been raised with the requirement of second order self-appraisal for autonomy. For it is unclear that such higher level judgments have any greater claim to authenticity than their first order cousins. Clearly if a person is manipulated or oppressed (and hence non-autonomous), it could well be that the reflective judgments she makes about herself are just as tainted by that oppression as are her ground-level decisions (Thalberg 1989, Friedman 1986, Meyers 1989, 25–41, Noggle 2005), and often our second order reflective voices are merely rationalizations and acts of self-deception rather than true and settled aspects of our character (for general discussion see the essays in Veltman and Piper 2014). This has led to the charge that models of autonomy which demand second-order endorsement merely introduce an infinite regress: for second-level judgments must be tested for their authenticity in the same way as first order desires are, but if that is so, then ever higher levels of endorsement would be called for. Various responses to this problem have been made, for the most part involving the addition of conditions concerning the manner in which such reflection must be made, for example that it must be free of certain distorting factors itself, it must reflect an adequate causal history, and the like (Christman 1991, Mele 1995).

Other aspects of the inner reflection model should be noted. As just mentioned, this view of autonomy is often stated as requiring critical self reflection (see, e.g., Haworth 1986). This has been understood as involving a rational appraisal of one’s desires, testing them for internal consistency, their relation to reliable beliefs, and the like. But an overly narrow concentration on rational assessment exposes such conceptions to charges of hyper intellectualism, painting a picture of the autonomous person as a cold, detached calculator (see Meyers 2004, 111–37). Connections to values, desires, and personal traits are often grounded in emotional and affective responses, ones connected with care, commitment, and relations to others (see Friedman 1998, MacKenzie & Stoljar 2000b, Meyers 1989, de Calleja, Mirja Perez 2019). For parallel reasons, some theorists have noted that concentration on only desires as the focal point of autonomy is overly narrow, as people can (fail to) exhibit self-government relative to a wide range of personal characteristics, such as values, physical traits, relations to others, and so on (see Double 1992, 66).

2. Autonomy in Moral Philosophy

Autonomy is central in certain moral frameworks, both as a model of the moral person — the feature of the person by virtue of which she is morally obligated — and as the aspect of persons which grounds others’ obligations to her or him. For Kant, the self-imposition of universal moral law is the ground of both moral obligation generally and the respect others owe to us (and we owe ourselves). In short, practical reason — our ability to use reasons to choose our own actions — presupposes that we understand ourselves as free. Freedom means lacking barriers to our action that are in any way external to our will, though it also requires that we utilize a law to guide our decisions, a law that can come to us only by an act of our own will (for further discussion see Hill 1989; for doubts about this reading, see Kleingeld and Willaschek 2019). This self-imposition of the moral law is autonomy. And since this law must have no content provided by sense or desire, or any other contingent aspect of our situation, it must be universal. Hence we have the (first formulation of the) Categorical Imperative, that by virtue of our being autonomous we must act only on those maxims that we can consistently will as a universal law.

The story continues, however: for the claim is that this capacity (to impose upon ourselves the moral law) is the ultimate source of all moral value — for to value anything (instrumentally or intrinsically) implies the ability to make value judgments generally, the most fundamental of which is the determination of what is morally valuable. Some theorists who are not (self-described) Kantians have made this inference central to their views of autonomy. Paul Benson, for example, has argued that being autonomous implies a measure of self-worth in that we must be in a position to trust our decision-making capacities to put ourselves in a position of responsibility (Benson 1994; cf. also Grovier 1993, Lehrer 1997, and Westlund 2014). But the Kantian position is that such self-regard is not a contingent psychological fact about us, but an unavoidable implication of the exercise of practical reason (cf. Taylor 2005).

So we owe to ourselves moral respect in virtue of our autonomy. But insofar as this capacity depends in no way on anything particular or contingent about ourselves, we owe similar respect to all other persons in virtue of their capacity. Hence (via the second formulation of the Categorical Imperative), we are obliged to act out of fundamental respect for other persons in virtue of their autonomy. In this way, autonomy serves as both a model of practical reason in the determination of moral obligation and as the feature of other persons deserving moral respect from us. (For further discussion, see Immanual Kant and moral philosophy .)

Recent discussions of Kantian autonomy have downplayed the transcendental nature of practical reason in this account (see, for example, Herman 1993 and Hill 1991). For example, Christine Korsgaard follows Kant in seeing our capacity for self-reflection as both the object of respect and the seat of normativity generally. On her view, we are all guided by what she calls a “practical identity”, a point of view which orients reflection on values and manifests an aspect of our self concept. But unlike Kant, Korsgaard argues that we have different practical identities that are the source of our normative commitments, and not all of them are of fundamental moral worth. But the most general of such identities — that which makes us members of a kingdom of ends — is our moral identity, which yields universal duties and obligations independent of contingent factors. Autonomy is the source of all obligations, whether moral or non-moral, since it is the capacity to impose upon ourselves, by virtue of our practical identities, obligations to act (Korsgaard 1996).

Traditional critiques of autonomy-based moral views, and Kant’s in particular, have been mounted along various lines. I mention two here, as they connect with issues concerning autonomy in social and political theory. The first concerns the way in which autonomy-based moral theory grounds obligation in our cognitive abilities rather than in our emotions and affective connections (see, e.g., Williams 1985, Stocker 1976). The claim is that Kantian morality leaves too little room for the kinds of emotional reactions that are constitutive of moral response in many situations: the obligations of parents for example concern not only what they do but the passions and care they bring forth in doing it. To view obligation as arising from autonomy but understanding autonomy in a purely cognitive manner makes such an account vulnerable to this kind of charge.

The difficulty this criticism points to resides in the ambiguities of the self-description that we might utilize in valuing our “humanity” — our capacity to obligate ourselves. For we can reflect upon our decision-making capacities and value this positively (and fundamentally) but regard that “self” engaging the capacity in different ways. The Kantian model of such a self is of a pure cognizer — a reflective agent engaged in practical reason. But also involved in decision-making are our passions — emotions, desires, felt commitments, senses of attraction and aversion, alienation and comfort. These are both the objects of our judgement and partly constitutive of them — to passionately embrace an option is different from cooly determining it to be best. Judgment is involved with all such passions when decisions are made. And it (judgment) need not be understood apart from them, but as an ability to engage in those actions whose passionate and reasoned support we muster up. So when the optimal decision for me is an impassioned one, I must value my ability to engage in the right passions, not merely in the ability to cold-heartedly reflect and choose. Putting the passions outside the scope of reasoned reflection, as merely an ancillary quality of the action — to consider how to do something not merely what we are doing — is to make one kind of decision. Putting passions inside that scope — saying that what it is right to do now is to act with a certain affect or passion — is another. When we generalize from our ability to make the latter sort of decisions, we must value not only the ability to weigh options and universalize them but also the ability to engage the right affect, emotion, etc. Therefore, we value ourselves and others as passionate reasoners not merely reasoners per se.

The implication of this observation is that in generalizing our judgments in the manner Korsgaard (following Kant) says we must, we need not commit ourselves to valuing only the cognitive capacities of humanity but also its (relatively) subjective elements.

A second question is this: since the reflection that is involved in autonomy (and which, according to this view, is the source of normativity) need only be hypothetical reflection upon one’s desires and mental capacities, then the question arises: under what conditions is this hypothetical reflection meant to take place? If the capacity for reflection is the seat of obligation, then we must ask if the conditions under which such hypothetical reflection takes place are idealized in any sense — if they are assumed to be reasonable for example. Are we considering merely the reflections the (actual) person would make were she to turn her attention to the question, no matter how unreasonable such reflections might be? If so, why should we think this grounds obligations? If we assume they are reasonable, then under some conditions moral obligations are not imposed by the actual self but rather by an idealized, more rational self. This implies that morality is not literally self-imposed if by “self” one means the actual set of judgments made by the agent in question. Indeed, a Platonist/realist about moral value could claim that the objective values which (according to the theory) apply to all agents independent of choice are in fact “self-imposed” in this idealized sense: they would be imposed were the person to reflect on the matter, acting as a perfectly reasonable agent. This shows the complex and potentially problematic implications of this ambiguity.

This points to the question of whether autonomy can be the seat of moral obligation and respect if autonomy is conceived in a purely procedural manner. If no substantive commitments or value orientations are included in the conceptual specification of autonomy, then it is unclear how this capacity grounds any particular substantive value commitments. On the other hand, if autonomy includes a specification of particular values in its conditions — that the autonomous person must value her own freedom for example — then it turns out that moral obligation (and respect) attaches only to those already committed in this way, and not more generally to all rational agents as such (as traditionally advertised by the view). This echoes, of course, Hegel’s critique of Kant.

These difficulties point to ambiguities in autonomy-based moral views, ones which may well be clarified in further developments of those theories. They also pick up on traditional problems with Kantian ethics (though there are many other such difficulties not mentioned here). Before leaving moral philosophy, we should consider ethical views which focus on autonomy but which do not depend directly on a Kantian framework.

Autonomy can play a role in moral theory without that theory being fully Kantian in structure. For example, it is possible to argue that personal autonomy has intrinsic value independent of a fully worked out view of practical reason. Following John Stuart Mill, for example, one can claim that autonomy is “one of the elements of well-being” (Mill 1859/1975, ch. III). Viewing autonomy as an intrinsic value or as a constitutive element in personal well-being in this way opens the door to a generally consequentialist moral framework while paying heed to the importance of self-government to a fulfilling life (for discussion see Sumner 1996).

It may also be unclear why autonomy — viewed here as the capacity to reflect on and endorse one’s values, character and commitments — should have value independent of the results of exercising that capacity. Why is one person’s autonomy intrinsically valuable when she uses it to, say, harm herself or make rash or morally skewed choices? More generally, how can we take account of the systematic biases and distortions that plague typical human reasoning in valuing people’s capacity to make decisions for themselves (see, e.g., Conly 2013)? This question becomes more acute as we consider ways that autonomy can obtain in degrees, for then it is unclear why personal autonomy should be seen as equally valuable in persons who display different levels of it (or different levels of those abilities that are its conditions, such as rationality).

Indeed, autonomy is often cited as the ground of treating all individuals equally from a moral point of view. But if autonomy is not an all-or-nothing characteristic, this commitment to moral equality becomes problematic (Arneson 1999). It can be argued that insofar as the abilities required for autonomy, such as rational reflectiveness, competences in carrying out one’s decisions, and the like, vary across individuals (within or between species as well), then it is difficult to maintain that all autonomous beings have equal moral status or that their interests deserve the same weight in considering decisions that affect them.

The move that must be made here, I think, picks up on Korsgaard’s gloss on Kantianism and the argument that our reflective capacities ultimately ground our obligations to others and, in turn, others’ obligations to regard us as moral equals. Arneson argues, however, that people surely vary in this capacity as well — the ability to reflectively consider options and choose sensibly from among them. Recall what we said above concerning the ambiguities of Korsgaard’s account concerning the degree to which the self-reflection that grounds obligation is idealized at all. If it is, then it is not the everyday capacity to look within ourselves and make a choice that gives us moral status but the more rarified ability to do so rationally, in some full sense. But we surely vary in our ability to reach that ideal, so why should our autonomy be regarded as equally worthy?

The answer may be that our normative commitments do not arise from our actual capacities to reflect and to choose (though we must have such capacities to some minimal degree), but rather from the way in which we must view ourselves as having these capacities. We give special weight to our own present and past decisions, so that we continue on with projects and plans we make because (all other things being equal) we made them, they are ours, at least when we do them after some reflective deliberation. The pull that our own decisions have on our ongoing projects and actions can only be explained by the assumption that we confer status and value on decisions simply because we reflectively made them (perhaps, though, in light of external, objective considerations). This is an all-or-nothing capacity and hence may be enough to ground our equal status even if perhaps, in real life, we exercise this capacity to varying degrees. [ 3 ] Much has been written about conceptions of well being that rehearse these worries (see Sumner 1996, Griffin 1988). Such a view might be buttressed with the idea that the attribution of autonomous agency, and the respect that purportedly goes with it, is itself a normative stance, not a mere observation of how a person actually thinks and acts (for discussion of this position see Christman 2009, chap. 10 and Korsgaard 2014)

Autonomy is the aspect of persons that undue paternalism offends against. Paternalistic interventions can be both interpersonal (governed by social and moral norms) and a matter of policy (mediated by formal or legal rules). Such interventions are identified not by the kind of acts they involve but by the justification given for them, so that paternalism involves interference with a person’s actions or knowledge against that person’s will for the purpose of advancing that person’s good. Respect for autonomy is meant to prohibit such interventions because they involve a judgment that the person is not able to decide for herself how best to pursue her own good. Autonomy is the ability to so decide, so for the autonomous subject of such interventions paternalism involves a lack of respect for autonomy. See also Paternalism .

But as our discussion of the nature of autonomy indicated, it is often unclear exactly what that characteristic involves. Important in this context is whether autonomy can be manifested in degrees — whether the abilities and capacities that constitute autonomy obtain all at once or progressively, or I can enjoy sufficient autonomy in some areas of my life but not in others. If autonomy is a matter of degree in any of these ways, then it is unclear that a blanket prohibition against paternalism is warranted. Some people will be less able to judge for themselves what their own good is and hence be more susceptible to (justified) paternalistic intervention (Conly 2013; see also Killmister 2017, chap. 7).

Often such an obligation toward another person requires us to treat her as autonomous, independent of the extent to which she is so concerning the choice in question. At least this is the case when a person is autonomous above a certain threshold: she is an adult, not under the influence of debilitating factors, and so on. I might know that a person is to some degree under the sway of external pressures that are severely limiting her ability to govern her life and make independent choices. But as long as she has not lost the basic ability to reflectively consider her options and make choices, if I intervene against her will (for her own good), I show less respect for her as a person than if I allow her to make her own mistakes. (Which is not to say, of course, that intervention in such cases might not, in the end, be justified; only that something is lost when it is engaged in, and what is lost is a degree of interpersonal respect we owe each other.)

However, as we saw in the last section, this move depends on the determination of basic autonomy and an argument that such a threshold is non-arbitrary. Also relevant here is the question of procedural versus substantive autonomy as the ground of the prohibition of paternalism. For if by “autonomy” we mean the ability to govern oneself no matter how depraved or morally worthless are the options being exercised, it is unclear that the bar to paternalism (and respect for persons generally) retains its normative force. As I mentioned above, the response to this challenge must be that the decision making capacity itself is of non-derivative value, independent of the content of those decisions, at least if one wishes to avoid the difficulties of positing a substantive (and hence non-neutral) conception of autonomy as the basis for interpersonal respect.

This is merely a sampling of some of the central ways that the idea of autonomy figures in moral philosophy. Not discussed here are areas of applied ethics, for example in medical ethics, where respect for autonomy grounds such principles as that of informed consent. Such contexts illustrate the fundamental value that autonomy generally is thought to represent as expressive of one of the fundamentals of moral personhood.

3. Autonomy in Social and Political Philosophy

The conception of the autonomous person plays a variety of roles in various constructions of liberal political theory (for recent discussion, see, e.g., Coburn 2010, Christman 2015 and the essays in Christman and Anderson, eds. 2005). Principally, it serves as the model of the person whose perspective is used to formulate and justify political principles, as in social contract models of principles of justice (Rawls 1971). Also (and correspondingly) it serves as the model of the citizen whose basic interests are reflected in those principles, such as in the claim that basic liberties, opportunities, and other primary goods are fundamental to flourishing lives no matter what moral commitments, life plans, or other particulars of the person might obtain (Kymlicka 1989, 10–19, Waldron 1993: 155–6). [ 4 ] Moreover, autonomy is ascribed to persons (or projected as an ideal) in order to delineate and critique oppressive social conditions, liberation from which is considered a fundamental goal of justice (whether or not those critiques are described as within the liberal tradition or as a specific alternative to it) (cf. Keornahan 1999, Cornell 1998, Young 1990, Gould 1988; cf. also Hirschmann 2002, 1–29).

For our purposes here, liberalism refers generally to that approach to political power and social justice that determines principles of right (justice) prior to, and largely independent of, determination of conceptions of the good (though see Liberalism ; see also Christman 2017, ch. 4). This implies that the liberal conception of justice, and the legitimation of political power more generally, can be specified and justified without crucial reference to controversial conceptions of value and moral principles (what Rawls calls “comprehensive moral conceptions” (Rawls 1993, 13–15). The fact of permanent pluralism of such moral conceptions is therefore central to liberalism. [ 5 ]

One manner in which debates concerning autonomy directly connect to controversies within and about liberalism concerns the role that state neutrality is to play in the justification and application of principles of justice. Neutrality is a controversial standard, of course, and the precise way in which liberal theory is committed to a requirement of neutrality is complex and controversial (see Raz 1986, 110–64, Waldron 1993, 143–67). The question to be asked here is whether the conception of autonomy utilized in liberal theories must itself attempt to be neutral concerning various conceptions of morality and value, or, alternatively, does the reliance on autonomy in the justification and specification of liberal theories of justice render them non-neutral simply because of this reliance (no matter how “neutral” the conception of autonomy utilized turns out to be) (Christman 2015).

Let us consider this first question and in so doing revisit the issue of whether the independence implicit in autonomy should best be conceived in a purely “procedural” manner or more substantively. Recall that some theorists view autonomy as requiring minimal competence (or rationality) along with authenticity, where the latter condition is fleshed out in terms of the capacity to reflectively accept motivational aspects of oneself. This view can be called “proceduralist” because it demands that the procedure by which a person comes to identify a desire (or trait) as her own is what is crucial in the determination of its authenticity and hence autonomy. This conception of autonomy is adopted, according to its defenders, because doing so is the only way to ensure that autonomy is neutral toward all conceptions of value and the good that reasonable adults may come to internalize (Dworkin 1989, Freyenhage 2017).

Critics of this view have pointed to cases where it is imagined that persons adopt what we all would call oppressive and overly restrictive life situations but in a way that meets the minimal conditions of autonomy on proceduralist accounts, so that on such accounts they count as autonomous because of the self-governing processes by which they entered such oppressive conditions. These critics argue that any conception of autonomy that ascribes that trait to such people is wrongly conceived (Benson 1987, MacKenzie & Stoljar 2001b and 2017, Waller 1993, and Oshana 1998). On the basis of such a judgment, they argue that normatively substantive conditions should be added to the requirements of autonomy, conditions such as the ability to recognize and follow certain moral or political norms (See Benson 1987, Wolf 1980; for criticism, see Berofsky 1995, ch. 7). This criticism suggests that considerations concerning the autonomous self cannot avoid questions of identity and hence whether the self of self-government can be understood independently of the (perhaps socially defined) values in terms of which people conceive of themselves; this is a subject to which we now turn.

Autonomy, as we have been describing it, certainly attaches paradigmatically to individual persons; it is not (in this usage) a property of groups or peoples. So the autonomy that grounds basic rights and which connects to moral responsibility, as this concept is thought to do, is assigned to persons without essential reference to other people, institutions, or traditions within which they may live and act. Critics claim, however, that such a view runs counter to the manner in which most of us (or all of us in some ways) define ourselves, and hence diverges problematically from the aspects of identity that motivate action, ground moral commitments, and by which people formulate life plans. Autonomy, it is argued, implies the ability to reflect wholly on oneself, to accept or reject one’s values, connections, and self-defining features, and change such elements of one’s life at will. But we are all not only deeply enmeshed in social relations and cultural patterns, we are also defined by such relations, some claim(Sandel 1982, 15–65). For example, we use language to engage in reflection but language is itself a social product and deeply tied to various cultural forms. In any number of ways we are constituted by factors that lie beyond our reflective control but which nonetheless structure our values, thoughts, and motivations (Taylor 1991, 33f; for discussion see Bell 1993, 24–54). To say that we are autonomous (and hence morally responsible, bear moral rights, etc.) only when we can step back from all such connections and critically appraise and possibly alter them flies in the face of these psychological and metaphysical realities. [ 6 ]

In a different manner, critics have claimed that the liberal conception of the person, reflected in standard models of autonomy, under-emphasizes the deep identity-constituting connections we have with gender, race, culture, and religion, among other things. Such “thick” identities are not central to the understanding of the self-governing person who, according to standard liberal models, is fully able to abstract from such elements of her self-concept and to either identify with or to reject such them. But such an ideal too narrowly valorizes the life of the cosmopolitan “man” — the world traveler who freely chooses whether to settle into this or that community, identify with this or that group, and so on (see Young 1991, Alcoff 2006 and Appiah 2010; for discussion, see Meyers, 2000b).

These challenges have also focused on the relation of the self to its culture (Margalit and Raz, 1990, Tamir 1993). What is at issue from a policy perspective is that emphasis on the individual’s self-government, with the cosmopolitan perspective that this entails, makes it difficult if not impossible to ground rights to the protection and internal self- government of traditional cultures themselves (Kymlicka, 1995). This is problematic in that it excludes from the direct protection of liberal policies those individuals and groups whose self-conceptions and value commitments are deeply constituted by cultural factors. Or, conversely, the assumption that the autonomous person is able to separate himself from all cultural commitments forestalls moves to provide state protection for cultural forms themselves, insofar as such state policies rest on the value of autonomy.

There have been many responses to these charges on behalf of a liberal outlook (e.g., Kymlicka, 1989, Gutman, 1985, Appiah 2005; for a general response to question of cultural identities see Kymlicka 1997). The most powerful response is that autonomy need not require that people be in a position to step away from all of their connections and values and to critically appraise them. Mere piecemeal reflection is all that is required. As Kymlicka puts it: “No particular task is set for us by society, and no particular cultural practice has authority that is beyond individual judgement and possible rejection” (Kymlicka, 1989:, 50).

There is a clarification that is needed in this exchange, however. For insofar as defenders of liberal principles (based on the value of autonomy) claim that all aspects of a person’s self-concept be subject to alteration in order to manifest autonomy, they needlessly exaggerate the commitments of the liberal position. For such a view is open to the charge that liberal conceptions fail to take seriously the permanent and unalterable aspects of the self and its social position (Young, 1990, 46). Our embodiment, for example, is often not something which we can alter other than marginally, and numerous other self-defining factors such as sexual orientation (for some), native language, culture and race, are not readily subject to our manipulation and transformation, even in a piecemeal manner. To say that we are heteronomous because of this is therefore deeply problematic. What must be claimed by the defender of autonomy-based liberalism is that the ability in question is to change those aspects of oneself from which one is deeply alienated (or with which one does not identify, etc.). For in those cases where, upon reflection, one experiences one’s body, culture, race, or sexuality as an external burden constricting one’s more settled and authentic nature, and still one cannot alter that factor, then one lacks autonomy relative to it (see Christman,2009 ch. 6). But if one feels fully at home within those unalterable parameters one does not lack autonomy because of that unalterability (for a different way of approach this issue see Mahmoud 2005 and Khader 2011).

As we said, several writers have claimed that proceduralist accounts of autonomy would wrongly attribute autonomy to those whose restricted socialization and stultifying life conditions pressure them into internalizing oppressive values and norms, for example women who have internalized the belief in the social authority of husbands, or that only by having and raising children are their lives truly complete, and the like. If such women reflect on these values they may well endorse them, even if doing so is free of any specific reflection-inhibiting conditions. But such women surely lack autonomy, it is claimed; so only if autonomy includes a requirement that one be able to recognize basic value claims (such as the person’s own equal moral standing) will that concept be useful in describing the oppressive conditions of a patriarchal society (see, e.g., Oshana, 1998, Stoljar, 2000; for discussion see Christman 2009 chap. 8, Benson, 1990, Friedman, 2000, Meyers, 1987, 1989). [ 7 ]

These and related considerations have sparked some to develop an alternative conception of autonomy meant to replace allegedly overly individualistic notions. This replacement has been called “relational autonomy” (MacKenzie and Stoljar, 2000a). Spurred by feminist critiques of traditional conceptions of autonomy and rights (Nedelsky, 1989, Code, 1991), relational conceptions of autonomy stress the ineliminable role that relatedness plays in both persons’ self- conceptions, relative to which autonomy must be defined, and the dynamics of deliberation and reasoning. These views offer a provocative alternative to traditional models of the autonomous individual, but it must be made clear what position is being taken on the issue: on the one hand, relational accounts can be taken as resting on a non-individualist conception of the person and then claim that insofar as autonomy is self-government and the self is constituted by relations with others, then autonomy is relational; or these accounts may be understood as claiming that whatever selves turn out to be, autonomy fundamentally involves social relations rather than individual traits (Oshana, 2006). Some such views also waiver between claiming that social and personal relations play a crucial causal role in the development and enjoyment of autonomy and claiming that such relations constitute autonomy (for discussion see Mackenzie and Stoljar, 2000b, 21–26; for a recent overview, see Mackenzie 2014).

Another relational element to autonomy that has been developed connects social support and recognition of the person’s status to her capacities for self-trust, self-esteem, and self-respect. The core argument in these approaches is that autonomy requires the ability to act effectively on one’s own values (either as an individual or member of a social group), but that oppressive social conditions of various kinds threaten those abilities by removing one’s sense of self-confidence required for effective agency. Social recognition and/or support for this self-trusting status is required for the full enjoyment of these abilities (see Anderson and Honneth 2005, Grovier 1993, Benson 2005, McCleod and Sherwin 2005, and Westlund 2014).

These claims often are accompanied with a rejection of purportedly value-neutral, proceduralist accounts of autonomy, even those that attempt to accommodate a fully social conception of the self. One question that arises with relational views connected to self-trust in this way: why, exactly are such relations seen as conceptually constitutive of autonomy rather than contributory to it (and its development), where the self-confidence or self-trust in question is the core element to which these sorts of social relations are an important (albeit contingent) contributor. Another question to be considered arises from those cases where self-trust is established despite lack of social recognition, as when runaway slaves manage to heroically push on with their quest for freedom while facing violent denials from surrounding others (and surrounding social structures) that they enjoy the status of a full human being capable of authentic decision making. Finally, self-trust is not always merited: consider the brash teenager who insists on exercising social independence based on her unwarranted confidence in her abilities to make good judgments (see Mackenzie 2008, n. 36).

Nevertheless, these approaches have all importantly shifted philosophical attention concerning autonomy to the social and interpersonal dynamics that shape its enjoyment, connecting ideas about autonomy with broader issues of social justice, recognition, and social practices. This brings us back, then, to considerations of the liberal project and its potential limitations, where autonomy remains central.

3.4 Autonomy, Liberalism, and Perfectionism

As noted earlier, there are various versions of liberal political philosophy. All of them, however, are committed to a conception of political legitimacy in which political power and authority is justified only if such authority is acceptable to all citizens bound by it (see Rawls 1993, 144–50). This connects to a broader view of the foundations of value that at least some liberal theorists present as central to that tradition. That is the claim that values are valid for a person only if those values are or can be reasonably endorsed by the person in question. By extension, principles guiding the operation of institutions of social and political power — what Rawls calls the institutions of the basic structure (Rawls 1993, 258) — are legitimate only if they can be endorsed in this way by those subject to them. In this way, liberalism (in most of its forms) is committed to what some have called the “endorsement constraint” (Kymlicka 1989, 12f, R. Dworkin 2000, 216–18).

Models of autonomy considered above include a condition that mirrors this constraint, in that a person is autonomous relative to some action-guiding norm or value only if, upon critical reflection of that value, she identifies with it, approves of it, or does not feel deeply alienated from it. Combining this view with the endorsement constraint, liberalism carries the implication that autonomy is respected only when guiding values or principles in a society can be embraced in some way by those governed by them. This will connect directly to the liberal theory of legitimacy to be discussed below.

Perfectionists reject this set of claims. Perfectionism is the view that there are values valid for an individual or a population even when, from the subjective point of view of those agents or groups, that value is not endorsed or accepted (Wall 1998, Sumner 1996, 45–80, Hurka 1993, Sher 1997; see also Perfectionism ). In short, it is the view that there are entirely objective values. While there are perfectionist liberals, this view generally resists the liberal claim that the autonomous acceptance of the central components of political principles is a necessary condition for the legitimacy of those principles. Moreover, perfectionists question the liberal commitment to neutrality in the formulation and application of political principles (Hurka 1993, 158–60).

Perfectionists specifically target the liberal connection between respect for autonomy and neutrality of political principles (Wall 1998, 125–204). For many, liberalism rests on the value of individual autonomy, but this reliance either assumes that respect for autonomy is merely one value among others in the liberal view, or autonomy has overriding value. In either case, however, neutrality is not supported. If autonomy is merely one value among others, for example, then there will clearly be times when state support of those other values will override respect for autonomy (paternalistic restrictions imposed to promote citizen safety, for example) (Sher 1997, 45–105, Hurka 1993, 158–60, Conly 2013). On the other hand, autonomy could be seen as an absolute constraint on the promotion of values, or, more plausibly, as a constitutive condition of the validity of all values for a person, as the endorsement constraint implies. Perfectionists reply, however, that this is itself a controversial value position, one that may not find unqualified general support (Hurka 1993, 148–52, Sher 1997, 58–60, Sumner 1996, 174–83; cf. Griffin 1986, 135– 36). To answer these objections, one must turn to consideration of the liberal principle of legitimacy. For the claim that liberals make concerning the limits of state promotion of the good — a limit set by respect for autonomy — depends heavily on their view about the ultimate ground of political power.

Liberalism is generally understood to arise historically out of the social contract tradition of political philosophy and hence rests on the idea of popular sovereignty. The concept of autonomy, then, figures centrally in at least one dominant strand in this tradition, the strand the runs through the work of Kant. The major alternative version of the liberal tradition sees popular sovereignty as basically a collective expression of rational choice and that the principles of the basic institutions of political power are merely instrumental in the maximization of aggregate citizen welfare (or, as with Mill, a constitutive element of welfare broadly considered).

But it is the Kantian brand of liberalism that places autonomy of persons at center stage. Rawls’s Theory of Justice was seen as the contemporary manifestation of this Kantian approach to justice, where justice was conceived as those principles that would be chosen under conditions of unbiased rational decision-making (from behind the veil of ignorance). The original position where such principles would be chosen was said by Rawls to mirror Kant’s Categorical Imperative. That is, it is a device in which persons can choose principles to impose upon themselves in a way which is independent of contingencies of social position, race, sex, or conception of the good (Rawls 1971, 221–27). But as is well known, the Kantian foundations of Rawls’s theory of justice rendered it vulnerable to the charge that it was inapplicable to those populations (all modern populations in fact) where deep moral pluralism abounds. For under such conditions, no theory of justice which rests on a metaphysically grounded conception of the person could claim full allegiance from members of a population whose deep diversity causes them to disagree about metaphysics itself, as well as about moral frameworks and conceptions of value related to it. For this reason, Rawls developed a new (or further developed) understanding of the foundations of his version of liberalism, a political conception (Rawls 1993).

Under political liberalism, autonomy of persons is postulated, not as a metaphysically grounded “fact” about moral personality or practical reason as such, but rather as one of several “device[s] of representation” under which diverse citizens can focus on the methods of derivation (such as the original position) for substantive principles of justice (Rawls 1999, 303–58). Justice is achieved only when an overlapping consensus among people moved by deeply divergent but reasonable comprehensive moral views can be attained, a consensus in which such citizens can affirm principles of justice from within those comprehensive views.

Political Liberalism shifts the focus from a philosophical conception of justice, formulated abstractly and meant to apply universally, to a practical conception of legitimacy where consensus is reached without pretension of deep metaphysical roots for the principles in question. More than merely a “modus vivendi” for the participating parties, justice must be affirmed in a way that finds a moral basis for all participating citizens, albeit from different frameworks of value and moral obligation. The operation of public reason, then, serves as the means by which such a consensus might be established, and hence public discussion and democratic institutions must be seen as a constitutive part of the justification of principles of justice rather than merely a mechanism for the collective determination of the social good.

But the role of autonomy in the specification of this picture should not be under- emphasized (or the controversies it invites ignored). For such a consensus counts as legitimate only when achieved under conditions of free and authentic affirmation of shared principles. Only if the citizens see themselves as fully able to reflectively endorse or reject such shared principles, and to do so competently and with adequate information and range of options, can the overlapping political consensus step beyond the purely strategic dynamics of a modus vivendi and ground legitimate institutions of political power.

Indeed, the assumption that all those subject to political authority enjoy the developed capacity to reflectively accept their life path and the values inherent in it invokes a level of idealization that belies the conditions of many victims of past and ongoing oppression. This virtually ensures that such structural conditions of society as racial domination, profound inequality of power, and patterns of exclusion of groups from equal standing in social space will be assumed away as irrelevant to the question of legitimacy (Mills 2005).

Therefore, social conditions that hamper the equal enjoyment of capacities to reflectively consider and (if necessary) reject principles of social justice, due, say, to extreme poverty, disability, ongoing injustice and inequality, or the like, restrict the establishment of just principles. Autonomy, then, insofar as that concept picks out the free reflective choice operating in the establishment of legitimacy, is basic to, and presupposed by, even such non-foundational (political) conceptions of justice.

Critics of political liberalism arise from several quarters. However, among the objections to it that focus on autonomy are those that question whether a political conception of legitimacy that rests on shared values can be sustained without the validity of those values being seen as somehow objective or fundamental, a position that clashes with the purported pluralism of political liberalism. Otherwise, citizens with deeply conflicting worldviews could not be expected to affirm the value of autonomy except as a mere modus vivendi (see, e.g., Wall 2009; cf. also Larmore 2008, 146–6). A line of response to this worry that could be pursued would be one that claimed that values that amount to autonomy (in some conceptualization of that idea) are already functional in the social structures and cultural practices of otherwise defensible democratic practices (as well as some critical projects that emphasize oppression and domination, as we saw above). This point raises the issue, to which we now turn, of the connection between autonomy, political liberalism, and democracy.

In closing, we should add a word about the implications of political liberalism for the traditional division between liberal justice and democratic theory. I say “division” here, but different views of justice and democracy will convey very different conceptions of the relation between the two (see Christiano 1996, Lakoff 1996). But traditionally, liberal conceptions of justice have viewed democratic mechanisms of collective choice as essential but highly circumscribed by the constitutional provisions that principles of justice support. Individual rights and freedoms, equality before the law, and various privileges and protections associated with citizen autonomy are protected by principles of justice and hence not subject to democratic review, on this approach (Gutmann 1993).

However, liberal conceptions of justice have themselves evolved (in some strains at least) to include reference to collective discussion and debate (public reason) among the constitutive conditions of legitimacy. It could be claimed, then, that basic assumptions about citizens’ capacities for reflective deliberation and choice — autonomy — must be part of the background conditions against which an overlapping consensus or other sort of political agreement concerning principles of justice is to operate.

Some thinkers have made the connection between individual or “private” autonomy and collective or “public” legitimacy — prominent, most notably Habermas (Habermas 1994). On this view, legitimacy and justice cannot be established in advance through philosophical construction and argument, as was thought to be the case in natural law traditions in which classical social contract theory flourished and which is inherited (in different form) in contemporary perfectionist liberal views. Rather, justice amounts to that set of principles that are established in practice and rendered legitimate by the actual support of affected citizens (and their representatives) in a process of collective discourse and deliberation (see e.g., Fraser 1997, 11–40 and Young 2000). Systems of rights and protections (private, individual autonomy) will necessarily be protected in order to institutionalize frameworks of public deliberation (and, more specifically, legislation and constitutional interpretation) that render principles of social justice acceptable to all affected (in consultation with others) (Habermas 1994, 111).

This view of justice, if at all acceptable, provides an indirect defense of the protection of autonomy and, in particular, conceptualizing autonomy in a way that assumes reflective self- evaluation. For only if citizen participants in the public discourse that underlies justice are assumed to have (and provided the basic resources for having) capacities for competent self- reflection, can the public defense and discussion of competing conceptions of justice take place (cf. Gaus 1996, Parts II and III, Gaus 2011). Insofar as autonomy is necessary for a functioning democracy (considered very broadly), and the latter is a constitutive element of just political institutions, then autonomy must be seen as reflective self-appraisal (and, I would add, non-alienation from central aspects of one’s person) (see Cohen 2002, Richardson 2003, Christman 2015).

This approach to justice and autonomy, spelled out here in rough and general form, has certainly faced criticism. In particular, those theorists concerned with the multi-dimensional nature of social and cultural “difference” have stressed how the conception of the autonomous person assumed in such principles (as well as criteria for rational discourse and public deliberation) is a contestable ideal not internalized by all participants in contemporary political life (see, e.g., Brown 1995, Benhabib 1992). Others motivated by post-modern considerations concerning the nature of the self, rationality, language, and identity, are also suspicious of the manner in which the basic concepts operative in liberal theories of justice (“autonomy” for example) are understood as fixed, transparent, and without their own political presuppositions (see, e.g., Butler 1990; for general discussion see White 1990).

These charges are stated here much too generally to give an adequate response in this context. But the challenge remains for any theory of justice which rests on a presumption of the normative centrality of autonomy. To be plausible in a variously pluralistic social setting, one marked by ongoing histories of oppressive practices and institutions, such a view must avoid the twin evils of forcibly imposing a (reasonably) contested value on resistant citizens, on the one hand, and simply abandoning all normative conceptions of social order in favor of open ended struggle for power on the other. The view that individuals ought to be treated as, and given the resources to become, autonomous in one of the minimal senses outlined here will, I submit, be a central element in any political view that steers between the Scylla of oppressive forms of perfectionism and the Charybdis of interest-group power politics.

  • Alcoff, Linda Martin, 2006. Visible Identities: Race, Gender and the Self , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Appiah, Kwame Anthony, 2005. The Ethics of Identity , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 2010. Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers , New York: Norton.
  • Arneson, Richard, 1991. “Autonomy and Preference Formation,” in Jules Coleman and Allen Buchanan (eds.), In Harm’s Way: Essays in Honor of Joel Feinberg , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 42–73.
  • –––, 1999. “What, if Anything, Renders All Humans Morally Equal?,” in D. Jamieson (ed.), Singer and his Critics , Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 103–28.
  • Arpaly, Nomy, 2004. Unprincipled Virtue , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Baumann, Holgar, 2008. “Reconsidering Relational Autonomy. Personal Autonomy for Socially Embedded and Temporally Extended Selves,” Analyse and Kritik , 30: 445–468.
  • Bell, Daniel, 1993. Communitarianism and its Critics , Oxford: Clarendon.
  • Benhabib, Seyla, 1992. Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics , New York: Routledge.
  • Benn, Stanley, 1988. A Theory of Freedom , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Benson, Paul, 2005. “Feminist Intuitions and the Normative Substance of Autonomy,” in J.S. Taylor (ed.), pp. 124–42.
  • –––, 1994. “Autonomy and Self-Worth,” Journal of Philosophy , 91(12): 650–668.
  • –––, 1990. “Feminist Second Thoughts About Free Agency,” Hypatia , 5(3): 47–64.
  • –––, 1987. “Freedom and Value,” Journal of Philosophy , 84(9): 465–86.
  • Berlin, Isaiah, 1969. “Two Concepts of Liberty,” in Four Essays on Liberty , London: Oxford University Press, pp. 118–72.
  • Berofsky, Bernard, 1995. Liberation from Self , New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Brighouse, Harry, 2000. School Choice and Social Justice , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Brown, Wendy, 1995. States of Injury: Power and Freedom in Late Modernity , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Bushnell, Dana (ed.), 1995. Nagging Questions , Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Butler, Judith, 1990. Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity , New York: Routledge.
  • Christiano, Thomas, 1996. The Rule of the Many: Fundamental Issues in Democratic Theory , Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
  • Christiano, Thomas and John Christman (eds.), 2009. Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy , Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Christman, John, 1991. “Autonomy and Personal History,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy , 21(1): 1–24.
  • –––, 1995. “Feminism and Autonomy,” in Bushnell (ed.), pp. 17–39.
  • –––, 2017. Social and Political Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction , 2nd ed. London: Routledge.
  • –––, 2009. The Politics of Persons: Individual Autonomy and Socio-historical Selves , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2015. “Autonomy and Liberalism: A Troubled Marriage?” in Steven Wall (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Liberalism , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp.141–62.
  • ––– (ed.), 1989. The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Christman, John and Joel Anderson (eds.), 2005. Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism: New Essays , New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Cochran, David, 1999. The Color of Freedom , Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
  • Coburn, Ben, 2010. Autonomy and Liberalism , New York: Routledge.
  • Code, Lorraine, 1991. “Second Persons,” in What Can She Know? Feminist Theory and the Construction of Knowledge , Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
  • Cohen, Joshua, 1996. “Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy,” in Benhabib (ed.), pp. 95–119.
  • –––, 2002. “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy,” in James Bohman and William Rehg, eds., Deliberative Democracy , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 67–92.
  • Conly, Sarah, 2013. Against Autonomy: Justifying Coercive Paternalism , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Cornell, Drucilla, 1998. At the Heart of Freedom , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Crittenden, Jack, 1992. Beyond Individualism: Reconstituting the Liberal Self , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Crocker, Lawrence, 1980. Positive Liberty , The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Cuypers, Stefaan, 2001. Self-Identity and Personal Autonomy , Hampshire, UK: Ashgate.
  • Cuypers, Stefaan E. and Ishtiyaque Haji, 2008. “Educating for Well-Being and Autonomy,” Theory and Research in Education , 6(1): 71–93.
  • de Calleja, Mirja Perez, 2019. “Autonomy and Indoctrinaiton: Why We Need an Emotional Condition for Autonomous Reflective Endorsement,” Social Philosophy and Policy , 36(1): 192–210.
  • Double, Richard, 1992. “Two Types of Autonomy Accounts,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy , 22(1): 65–80.
  • Dworkin, Gerald, 1988. The Theory and Practice of Autonomy , New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Dworkin, Ronald, 2000. Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Elster, Jon, 1983. Sour Grapes , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Feinberg, Joel, 1986. Harm to Self. The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law (Volume 3), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 1989. “Autonomy,” in Christman, (ed.), pp. 27–53.
  • Fischer, John Martin (ed.), 1986. Moral Responsibility , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • Fischer, John Martin and Mark Ravizza, 1998. Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility , New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Flathman, Richard, 1989. Toward A Liberalism , Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • Frankfurt, Harry, 1987. “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person,” in The Importance of What We Care About , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p.11–25.
  • –––, 1992. “The Faintest Passion,” Proceedings and Addresses of the Aristotelian Society , 49: 113–45.
  • Freyenhagen, Fabian, 2017. “Autonomy’s Substance,” Journal of Applied Philosophy , 34(1): 114–129.
  • Friedman, Marilyn, 1986. “Autonomy and the Split-Level Self,” Southern Journal of Philosophy , 24(1): 19–35.
  • –––, 1997. “Autonomy and Social Relationships: Rethinking the Feminist Critique,” in Meyers, (ed.), pp. 40–61.
  • –––, 1998. “Feminism, Autonomy, and Emotion,” in Norms and Values: Essays on the Work of Virginia Held , Joram Graf Haber,(ed.), pp.37–45.
  • –––, 2000. “Autonomy, Social Disruption, and Women,” in MacKenzie and Stoljar, (eds.), pp. 35–51.
  • Gaus, Gerald F., 1996. Justificatory Liberalism , New York: Oxford University Press
  • –––, 2010. The Order of Public Reason: A Theory of Freedom and Morality in a Diverse and Bounded World , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Geuss, Raymond, 2001. “Liberalism and Its Discontents,” Political Theory , 30(3): 320–39.
  • Gilligan, Carol, 1982. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Gould, Carol, 1988. Rethinking Democracy: Freedom and Social Cooperation in Politics, Economy, and Society , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Gray, John, 1993. Post-Liberalism: Studies in Political Thought , New York: Routledge.
  • Griffin, James, 1988. Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement and Moral Importance , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Grovier, Trudy, 1993. “Self-Trust, Autonomy and Self-Esteem,” Hypatia , 8(1): 99–119.
  • Gutman, Amy, 1985. “Communitarian Critics of Liberalism,” Philosophy and Public Affairs , 14(3): 308–22.
  • –––, 1987. Democratic Education , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 1993. “Democracy,” in Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit (eds.), A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy , Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, pp. 411–21.
  • Habermas, Jürgen, 1994. Between Facts and Norms , William Rehg (trans.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Haworth, Lawrence, 1986. Autonomy: An Essay in Philosophical Psychology and Ethics , New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Herman, Barbara, 1993. The Practice of Moral Judgement , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Hill, Thomas, 1987. “The Importance of Autonomy,” in Kittay and Meyers (eds.), pp. 129–38.
  • –––, 1989. “The Kantian Conception of Autonomy,” in Christman (ed.), pp. 91–105.
  • –––, 1991. Autonomy and Self Respect , New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hirschmann, Nancy, 2002. The Subject of Freedom: Toward A Feminist Theory of Freedom , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Hurka, Thomas, 1993. Perfectionism , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Jaggar, Alison, 1983. Feminist Politics and Human Nature , Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanheld.
  • Kant, Immanuel, 1785 [1983]. Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals , in I. Kant , Ethical Philosophy , James W. Ellington (trans.), Indianapolis, IA: Hackett Publishing Co.
  • –––, 1797 [1999]. Metaphysical Elements of Justice , John Ladd (ed.), Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
  • Kernohan, Andrew, 1999. Liberalism, Equality, and Cultural Oppression , New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Khader, Serene, 2011. Adaptive Preferences and Women’s Empowerment , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Killmister, Suzy, 2017. Taking the Measure of Autonomy: A Four-Dimensional Theory of Self-Governance , New York: Routledge.
  • Kittay, Eva Feder and Diana T. Meyers, 1987. Women and Moral Theory , Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
  • Kleingeld, Pauline and Marcus Willaschek, 2019. “Autonomy Without Paradox: Kant, Self-Legislation and the Moral Law,” Philosophers’ Imprint , 19(7): 1–18.
  • Korsgaard, Christine M., 2014. “The Normative Constitution of Agency,” in Manuel Vargas and Gideon Yaffe (eds.), Rational and Social Agency: The Philosophy of Michael Bratman , New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 190–214.
  • –––, 1996. The Sources of Normativity , New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Kymlicka, Will, 1989. Liberalism, Community and Culture , Oxford: Clarendon.
  • Lakoff, Sanford, 1996. Democracy: History, Theory, Practice , Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
  • Larmore, Charles, 2008. The Autonomy of Morality , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Lehrer, Keith, 1997. Self-Trust: A Study in Reason, Knowledge, and Autonomy , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • MacIntyre, Alasdair, 1984. After Virtue , Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
  • Mackenzie, Catriona, 2008. “Relational Autonomy, Normative Authority and Perfectionism,” Journal of Social Philosophy , 39(4): 512–33.
  • –––, 2014. “Three Dimensions of Autonomy: A Relational Analysis,” in Veltman and Piper (eds.),pp. 15–41.
  • Mackenzie, Catriona, and Natalie Stoljar (eds.), 2000a. Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2000b. “Introduction: Autonomy Refigured,” in Mackenzie and Stoljar (eds.), pp. 3–31.
  • MacKinnon, Catherine, 1989. Toward a Feminist Theory of the State , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Mahmoud, Saba, 2005. The Politics of Piety: The Islamic Revival and the Feminist Subject , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Margalit, Avashai and Joseph Raz, 1990. “National Self-Determination,” Journal of Philosophy , 87(9): 439–61.
  • May, Thomas, 1994. “The Concept of Autonomy,” American Philosophical Quarterly , 31(2): 133–44.
  • McCallum, Gerald, 1967. “Negative and Positive Freedom,” Philosophical Review , 76: 312–34.
  • McLeod, Carolyn and Susan Sherwin, 2000. “Relational Autonomy, Self-Trust, and Health Care for Patients Who Are Oppressed,” in MacKenzie and Stoljar (eds.), pp. 259–79.
  • Mele, Alfred R., 1991. “History and Personal Autonomy,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy , 23: 271–80.
  • –––, 1995. Autonomous Agents: From Self-Control to Autonomy , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Meyers, Diana T., 1987. “Personal Autonomy and the Paradox of Feminine Socialization,” Journal of Philosophy , 84: 619–28.
  • –––, 1989. Self, Society, and Personal Choice , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • –––, 1994. Subjection and Subjectivity: Psychoanalytic Feminism and Moral Philosophy , New York: Routledge.
  • ––– (ed.), 1997. Feminist Rethink the Self , Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
  • –––, 2004. Being Yourself: Essays on Identity, Action, and Social Life , Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
  • Mill, John Stuart, 1859 [1975]. On Liberty , David Spitz (ed.), New York: Norton.
  • Mills, Charles, 1997. The Racial Contract , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 2005. “‘Ideal Theory’ as Ideology,” Hypatia , 20(3): 165–83.
  • Moon, J. Donald, 1993. Constructing Community: Moral Pluralism and Tragic Conflicts , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Nedelsky, Jennifer, 1989. “Reconcieving Autonomy: Sources, Thoughts, and Possibilities,” Yale Journal of Law and Feminism , 1(1): 7–36.
  • Nicholson, Linda (ed.), 1990. Feminism/Postmodernism , New York: Routledge.
  • Noggle, R., 2005. “Autonomy and the Paradox of Self-Creation: Infinite Regresses, Finite Selves, and the Limits of Authenticity,” in J.S. Taylor (ed.), pp. 87–108.
  • O’Neill, Onora, 1989. Constructions of Reason: Explorations in Kant’s Practical Philosophy , New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Oshana, Marina, 1998. “Personal Autonomy and Society,” Journal of Social Philosophy , 29(1): 81–102.
  • –––, 2006. Personal Autonomy in Society , Hampshire, UK: Ashgate.
  • –––, 2005. “Autonomy and Self Identity,” in Christman and Anderson (eds.), pp. 77–100.
  • Pearsall, Marilyn (ed.), 1986. Women and Values: Readings in Recent Feminist Philosophy , Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing.
  • Rawls, John, 1971. A Theory of Justice , revised ed. (1999) Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1993. Political Liberalism , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Raz, Joseph, 1986. The Morality of Freedom , Oxford: Clarendon.
  • Richardson, Henry, 2003. Democratic Autonomy: Public Reasoning about the Ends of Policy , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Ripstein, Arthur, 1999. Equality, Responsibility, and the Law , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Rosich, Gerard, 2019. The Contested History of Autonomy: Interpreting European Modernity , London: Bloomsbury Academic.
  • Sandel, Michael J., 1982. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd ed., 1999.
  • Schneewind, J. B., 1998. The Invention of Autonomy , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Sher, George, 1997. Beyond Neutrality: Perfectionism and Politics , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Stoljar, Natalie, 2000. “Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition,” in Mackenzie and Stoljar (eds.), pp. 94–111.
  • –––, 2017. “Relational Autonomy and Perfectionism,” Moral Philosophy and Politics , 4(1): 27–41.
  • Sumner, L. W., 1996. Welfare, Happiness and Ethics , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Swaine, Lucas, 2016. “The Origins of Autonomy,” History of Political Thought , 37(2): 216–237.
  • Tamir, Yael, 1993. Liberal Nationalism , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Taylor, Charles, 1989. “Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate,” in Rosenblum (ed.), pp. 159–82.
  • –––, 1991. The Ethics of Authenticity , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1992. Multiculturalism and the “Politics of Recognition” , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Taylor, James Stacey (ed.), 2005. Personal Autonomy: New Essays on Personal Autonomy and Its Role in Contemporary Moral Philosophy , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Taylor, Robert, 2005. “Kantian Personal Autonomy,” Political Theory , 33(5): 602–628.
  • Thalberg, Irving, 1989. “Hierarchical Analyses of Unfree Action,” reprinted in Christman (ed.), pp. 123–136.
  • Veltman, Andrea and Mark Piper (eds.), 2014. Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Waldron, Jeremy, 1993. Liberal Rights: Collected Papers 1981–1991 , New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Wall, Steven, 1998. Liberalism, Perfectionism and Restraint , New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2009. “Perfectionism in Politics: A Defense,” in Christiano and Christman (eds.), pp. 99–118.
  • Westlund, Andrea, 2014. “Autonomy and Self-Care,” in Veltman and Piper (eds.), pp. 181–98.
  • White, Stephen, 1991. Political Theory and Post Modernism Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Williams, Bernard, 1985. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Wolf, Susan, 1990. Freedom and Reason , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Wolff, Robert Paul, 1970. In Defense of Anarchism , New York: Harper & Row.
  • Young, Iris Marion, 1990. Justice and the Politics of Difference , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 2000. Inclusion and Democracy , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Young, Robert, 1986. Autonomy: Beyond Negative and Positive Liberty , New York: St. Martin’s Press.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Autonomy , list of articles in the special issue (Vol. 20, No. 2, 2003) of Social Philosophy & Policy

autonomy: personal | communitarianism | feminist philosophy, topics: perspectives on the self | free will | identity politics | liberalism | paternalism | privacy | well-being

Copyright © 2020 by John Christman < jpc11 @ psu . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

The Autonomy Challenge: Examining the Pre-emption Thesis in Judicial Reasoning and Precedent

Profile image of Precedente Revista Jurídica

2023, Precedente Revista Jurídica

This article reflects on one of the challenges Gerald Postema’s account of the autonomy thesis poses to Raz’s pre-emption thesis in judicial practice and precedent. Certain flaws in the pre-emption thesis, as applied to courts, come to light upon analyzing the autonomy challenge, whereas some aspects of the former are better understood from the perspective of the latter. This work shows that, although these two theses seem to clash, the autonomy challenge leads instead to an alternative approach to the pre-emption thesis that allows exploring some disregarded relationships between judicial practical reasoning and precedent. Drawing from this Raz-Postema debate, I argue for an alternative reading of the autonomy challenge by introducing the hermeneutic strategy of courts (HeSCo) as a tool to analyze the role of officials as addressees of exclusionary legal directives and its explanatory force. The HeSCo ultimately unravels the paradox by holding the pre-emption thesis as central to the proper understanding of judicial practice and precedent.

Related Papers

Karina und Erich Schumann Centre for Advanced International Legal Studies Working Paper Series

Joseba K Fernández Gaztea

The answer of the CJEU to the question of the perimeter of its jurisdiction when EU law and a third law cooperate in a matter is not fully satisfactory. Departing from the traditional approach, both cases in which EU law is applied in close connection to international law, and also those in which it is applied in connection to national law should be considered because both are expressions of the same problem, namely: the trend of the Court to unionize third law, and on that ground to extend its jurisdiction beyond a straight reading of EU primary law and international law practice. The delimitation of its jurisdiction that the CJEU provides in these cases is neither precise, nor safe. Above all, the underlying assumption that EU law is just as autonomous as national law has to be accepted and needs to be re-explained as a law essentially interwoven with others. The challenge lies in reconciling its unity with its compound character. This attempt should shed light also on another aspect of legal protection: the exercise of power by different national administrations within the same procedure. The connection between the two issues is the fact that EU law and the exercise of EU power depend existentially on the contribution of national ones.

autonomy thesis pdf

Lenio Luiz Streck

The linguistic-ontological turn has brought uncountable consequences to the interpretation of Law. However, dogmatic-legal knowledge remains hostage to a judicial protagonism, a philosophy of consciousness that, together with legal discretion, represent two sides of the same coin. The criticism of judicial discretion is a matter of democracy: decisions must be coherent, assuring the integrity of Law by reinforcing the normative power of the Constitution from which arises the need for correct answers in Law.

The Yale Law Journal

David Trubek

Rafael Costa

This article focuses on the necessary interaction between law and ethics in interpretation of norms, arguing that the attitude of the judge, legislative impact assessment and the procedure to reach a decision, more than its content, should be taken into consideration to ensure (formal and material) legitimacy of decisions. The proposal to reconsider the problem of rationality and legitimacy of judicial decisions from the perspective of philosophical hermeneutics is very useful for a deeper understanding of the creative power of the judiciary, especially because it is impossible to guarantee the correct answer, which does not allow the interpreter to give any meaning to norms. It inaugurates a new approach, which prioritises questioning about the very phenomenon of hermeneutics (no longer limited to the study of suitable methods to discover the true meaning of the norm). Thus, this study seeks to understand the impact of revelations brought by philosophical hermeneutics to control creativity in Law, an issue chosen for debate by representing one of the great contemporary hermeneutical challenges. Considering the juspolitical function of supreme courts and the lessons of philosophical hermeneutics, I determine the role of hermeneutics in controlling judges' creativity and assuring that decisions are ethically grounded, arguably legitimate and rationally appropriate with the principle of separation of powers. Furthermore, I associate, in a democratic state, enforcement of fundamental rights with the rule that prohibits courts from acting as lawmakers.

Maciej Pichlak

The paper elaborates basic foundations for a new methodological account on autonomy of law. It argues that the problem of law’s autonomy, however broadly discussed in the past, still waits for a fully plausible and comprehensive examination. The main attempt is realized in three subsequent steps: firstly, the heretofore analyses of law’s autonomy are briefly recapitulate. Secondly, the main contemporary challenges in that field are pinpointed. These are: the increasing reflexivity of legal institutions, the growing (even if not explicitly indicated) relevance of the problem of law’s autonomy in jurisprudential debates of the date, and some theoretical deficiencies of existing analysis of the scrutinized problem; as to the last point, the existing analytical considerations should be complemented with more empirical, sociological insights. In the last, third step a research programme is proposed, based on the Sociological Discourse Analysis methodology. The main analytical tool herein is a concept of law-view, which is put forward and explained in the study.

Studies in Public Choice

Fabien Gelinas

Daniele Santoro , Federica Liveriero

Proceduralists hold that democracy has a non instrumental value, whose core consists in the ideal of equality incorporated by fair procedures. Against advocates of epistemic democracy, which justifies forms of epistocracy and denies the value of equality, proceduralists assume that ‘epistemic peerhood’ should be taken as a necessary baseline of equality. Epistemic peerhood is the idea that, within a collective decision framework, everybody has an equal likelihood of being mistaken (Peter 2008, 2013). Attempts of justifying this view often invoke the argument that epistemic peerhood inherits its value from a shared understanding of persons as having equal moral and reasoning powers, and therefore, any decision-making procedure that denies the equal likelihood of being fallible frustrates fairness. Yet, proceduralism does not license the conclusion that that every possible outcome of a democratic procedure is fair per se. This is the case when government and legislative decisions result from factional conflict, or depend on majoritarian dictatorships. In the non-ideal setting of actual constitutional democracies, Supreme Courts provide a guardianship of fundamental rights and liberties against contested outcomes of this sort by enacting mechanisms of check and balance, constitutional interpretation, and judicial review. Yet, in performing such a role, Supreme Courts exercise a form of epistocratic power, which is at odds with the principle of epistemic peerhood. In this paper, we argue that this is genuine normative dilemma for proceduralists: either they align with epistemic peerhood, and deny that any constitutional body may be conferred with special epistocratic privileges, or they defend the epistocratic role of Courts, giving up on peerhood. We analyse the dilemma and propose a solution, arguing that Supreme Courts do not run unrestrained decisions, but rather their decisional power is bound to the protective function of fundamental rights, in which their constitutional mandate ultimately consists.

Oñati Socio-Legal Series

Przemyslaw Tacik

In this paper I develop a theory of judicial subjectivity based on Lacan’s psychoanalysis. This theory is enriched with a theoretical confrontation with the abyssal laboratory of populist governance which has been created by the far-right majority in Poland since 2015. By adding this empirical context, I enquire how agency of judges is being created by the split legal system. The subjectivity of the judicial function implies speaking modestly in the name of the law, but at the same time involves being addressed by the demands of the Big Other. Yet at the same time the judge holds in her hands the jouissance of the law: it is the judge that can ultimately – with the effect of recognition within the Symbolic – acknowledge or refused validity of the law. It is in the judge’s subjectivity that the law can be recreated or can collapse. The peculiar link between the judge and her master is located in judicial conscience: the place where the subject’s structural emptiness corresponds to the lack within the law. As I argue in the paper, this role comes to the fore in case of split legal systems – such as the Polish one – which address judges with contradictory norms. In such moment the judge becomes ‘a judicial Antigone’ in Lacanian interpretation: a person on whose personal self-identification the legal system itself depends. Such a judicial Antigone – with empirical examples of Polish judges – is both the utmost hero and the utmost victim of the law.

N. Ir. Legal Q.

stefano bertea

Timothy Endicott

Can people be autonomous, if they are subject to authority? In particular, can they be autonomous if they are subject to the authority of law? I discuss the work of Joseph Raz on these questions, and argue that it offers a sound reconciliation of authority and autonomy, in which autonomous judgment is needed to determine the jurisdiction of an authority, and to determine the exclusionary scope of its directives. As for the particular question of the authority of law, Raz has said that law claims unlimited authority. I argue that although law may not acknowledge limits to its authority, it need not claim unlimited authority either. It claims an unspecified jurisdiction, and its directives may have unspecified exclusionary scope. People can be autonomous if they are subject to the authority of law: laws often violate autonomy, but there is nothing in the nature of law that violates autonomy. But its artificial, systematic nature creates a standing risk that the law of a particular system will do so.

RELATED PAPERS

Journal of Biological Chemistry

Jean-Francois Bouhours

Bernd Ulber

Journal of Indian Association for Child and Adolescent Mental Health

anuradha davey

Febrina Ramadhani

Cancers of the Head &amp; Neck

Carolyn Fang

Lecture Notes in Computer Science

Alain Giorgetti

麦克马斯特大学毕业证书 加拿大学历MMU文凭学位证书成绩单

Journal of Ethnopharmacology

María Alonso

Endang Setyati

Oman Medical Journal

Nazanin Mahdavi

Journal of Pediatric Surgery

Prabo Dwight

加拿大《Guelph证书》 圭尔夫大学毕业证

0882-2611-0625, Kontraktor Rumah Kayu

0882261100625 | Jasa Bangun Rumah

muhammad ilyas

suman singh

Critical Care

Materials Science and Engineering: B

NHAN HOA PHAM

Olle Findahl

Adrian Doko

RELATED TOPICS

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024
  • Search Menu

Sign in through your institution

  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Residential and Domestic Buildings
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Learning (Specific Skills)
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Language Acquisition
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethics in Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Culture
  • Music and Media
  • Music and Religion
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Construction Law
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Society
  • Law and Politics
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Study and Revision
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Neuroanaesthesia
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Oncology
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Medical Ethics
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Self-help and Personal Development
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Cell Biology
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Graphical and Digital Media Applications
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Electronics and Communications Engineering
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Ceramics and Glasses
  • Composite Materials
  • Metals, Alloying, and Corrosion
  • Nanotechnology
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business History
  • Business Ethics
  • Business Strategy
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and Government
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic History
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Applied Ecology (Social Science)
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • International Political Economy
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Theory
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Politics and Law
  • Politics of Development
  • Public Policy
  • Public Administration
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • East Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Land Forces and Warfare
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Naval Forces and Warfare
  • Other Warfare and Defence Issues
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution
  • Weapons and Equipment

Drawing Morals: Essays in Ethical Theory

  • < Previous chapter
  • Next chapter >

Drawing Morals: Essays in Ethical Theory

{ 8 } Why Value Autonomy?

  • Published: August 2011
  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

This chapter discusses the value of autonomy as an intrinsic good. Autonomy presupposes the human ideal of a person with knowledge and agency—the freedom to make a choice, as well as the knowledge to select morally good choices from a variety of options. In this way, autonomy provides the grounds for liberalism, which argues against state interference in the citizens' freedom of choice. However, some issues have to be considered: free choice is considered an intrinsic good, yet there is also a need to apply restrictions to autonomy in order to sometimes increase that autonomy. One can only infer that autonomy is intrinsically good, that any restrictions of this good will have moral consequences, and that there is always some reason to resist state interference with one's autonomy.

Signed in as

Institutional accounts.

  • GoogleCrawler [DO NOT DELETE]
  • Google Scholar Indexing

Personal account

  • Sign in with email/username & password
  • Get email alerts
  • Save searches
  • Purchase content
  • Activate your purchase/trial code
  • Add your ORCID iD

Institutional access

Sign in with a library card.

  • Sign in with username/password
  • Recommend to your librarian
  • Institutional account management
  • Get help with access

Access to content on Oxford Academic is often provided through institutional subscriptions and purchases. If you are a member of an institution with an active account, you may be able to access content in one of the following ways:

IP based access

Typically, access is provided across an institutional network to a range of IP addresses. This authentication occurs automatically, and it is not possible to sign out of an IP authenticated account.

Choose this option to get remote access when outside your institution. Shibboleth/Open Athens technology is used to provide single sign-on between your institution’s website and Oxford Academic.

  • Click Sign in through your institution.
  • Select your institution from the list provided, which will take you to your institution's website to sign in.
  • When on the institution site, please use the credentials provided by your institution. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.
  • Following successful sign in, you will be returned to Oxford Academic.

If your institution is not listed or you cannot sign in to your institution’s website, please contact your librarian or administrator.

Enter your library card number to sign in. If you cannot sign in, please contact your librarian.

Society Members

Society member access to a journal is achieved in one of the following ways:

Sign in through society site

Many societies offer single sign-on between the society website and Oxford Academic. If you see ‘Sign in through society site’ in the sign in pane within a journal:

  • Click Sign in through society site.
  • When on the society site, please use the credentials provided by that society. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.

If you do not have a society account or have forgotten your username or password, please contact your society.

Sign in using a personal account

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members. See below.

A personal account can be used to get email alerts, save searches, purchase content, and activate subscriptions.

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members.

Viewing your signed in accounts

Click the account icon in the top right to:

  • View your signed in personal account and access account management features.
  • View the institutional accounts that are providing access.

Signed in but can't access content

Oxford Academic is home to a wide variety of products. The institutional subscription may not cover the content that you are trying to access. If you believe you should have access to that content, please contact your librarian.

For librarians and administrators, your personal account also provides access to institutional account management. Here you will find options to view and activate subscriptions, manage institutional settings and access options, access usage statistics, and more.

Our books are available by subscription or purchase to libraries and institutions.

  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Rights and permissions
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

  • DSpace@MIT Home
  • MIT Libraries
  • Graduate Theses

Enabling tactical autonomy for unmanned surface vehicles in defensive swarm engagements

Thumbnail

Other Contributors

Terms of use, description, date issued, collections.

  • Undergraduate Theses

American University

Reflections on personal autonomy

One of the most intimate and problematic issues in philosophy is the matter of personal autonomy. It is intimate because most people care intensely about whether their decisions and way of life are autonomously chosen and lived. The issue of personal autonomy is problematic because the barriers to autonomous action can be subtle and unnoticeable. It is the thesis of this paper to discuss the nature of personal autonomy by (1) clarifying the concept of autonomy, (2) discussing the way in which autonomy can be realized, (3) presenting the views of five philosophers (Plato, Sartre, Hume, Mill, and Kant) in order to understand how one's understanding of human nature will affect one's understanding of personal autonomy, and lastly (4) to give reasons why we care about personal autonomy. The resources utilized in the research of this paper were the relevant books addressing the issue of personal autonomy from The American University and consortium libraries.

Access statement

Usage metrics.

Theses and Dissertations

Lucy Nyoroka Mworia Department of Social Sciences, St Paul’s University, Kenya

Wanjugu Wachira PhD, Department of Social Sciences, St Paul’s University, Kenya

Peter Mwaura PhD, Department of Social Sciences, St Paul’s University, Kenya

autonomy thesis pdf

..................................................

autonomy thesis pdf

Social Sciences Journals 

European Journal of Economic and Financial Research

European Journal of Management and Marketing Studies

European Journal of Human Resource Management Studies

European Journal of Political Science Studies

Public Health Journals

European Journal of Public Health Studies

European Journal of Fitness, Nutrition and Sport Medicine Studies

European Journal of Physiotherapy and Rehabilitation Studies

Education Journals    

European Journal of Education Studies

European Journal Of Physical Education and Sport Science

European Journal of Foreign Language Teaching

European Journal of English Language Teaching

European Journal of Special Education Research

European Journal of Alternative Education Studies

European Journal of Open Education and E-learning Studies

Literature, Language and Linguistics Journals

European Journal of Literature, Language and Linguistics Studies

European Journal of Literary Studies

European Journal of Applied Linguistics Studies

European Journal of Multilingualism and Translation Studies

........................................

autonomy thesis pdf

  • Other Journals
  • ##Editorial Board##
  • ##Indexing and Abstracting##
  • ##Author's guidelines##
  • ##Covered Research Areas##
  • ##Related Journals##
  • ##Manuscript submission##

JOB AUTONOMY AND EMPLOYEE PERFORMANCE IN THE COUNTY GOVERNMENT OF ISIOLO, KENYA

Article visualizations:

Hit counter

Abdi, A. (2018). Isiolo top officials sign annual performance contract. Retrieved from: https://www.standardmedia.co.ke/article/2001289103/isiolo-top-officials-sign-annual-performance-contract

Afshan S., Sobia I., Kamran, A. & Nasir, Mahmood (2012). Impact of Training on Employee Performance: A Study of Telecommunication Sector in Pakistan, Interdisciplinary Journal of Contemporary Research in Business, vol 4, no 6, pp. 646-661.

Aluvisia, H. K. (2016). Factors Influencing Employee Performance in the Kenyan Public Sector.

Basaza, M. (2016). Factors affecting the performance of employees at the ministry of health headquarters in Kampala, Uganda. Unpublished thesis Uganda Technology and management university.

Brink, A. G., Emerson, D. J., & Yang, L. (2016). Job autonomy and counterproductive behaviors in Chinese accountants: The role of job-related attitudes. Journal of International Accounting Research, 15(1), 115–131. https://doi.org/10.2308/jiar-51194

Burcharth, A., Præst Knudsen, M. and Søndergaard, H.A. (2017), "The role of employee autonomy for open innovation performance", Business Process Management Journal, Vol. 23 No. 6, pp. 1245-1269. https://doi.org/10.1108/BPMJ-10-2016-0209

County Government of Isiolo (2020). About us. Retrieved from; https://isiolo.go.ke/about-us-2/

Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (1985). Intrinsic motivation and self-determination in human behavior. New York, NY: Plenum.

Gillet, N., Colombat, P., Michinov, E., Pronost, A. M., & Fouquereau, E. (2013). Procedural justice, supervisor autonomy support, work satisfaction, organizational identification and job performance: The mediating role of need satisfaction and perceived organizational support. Journal of Advanced Nursing, 69(11), 2560-2571.

Gözükara, İ., & Çolakoğlu, N. (2016). Science Direct the Mediating Effect of Work Family Conflict on the Relationship between Job Autonomy and Job Satisfaction. Procedia-Social and Behavioral Sciences, 229, 253–266.

Jamil, M., Ahmad, K. and Nazir, B. (2016). Impact of Employee Socialization and Specialization on Job Rotation in Health Sector of Pakistan. International Journal of Economics and Empirical Research. 4(2), 88-93.

Jong, J. (2016). The role of performance feedback and job autonomy in mitigating the negative effect of role ambiguity on employee satisfaction. Public Performance & Management Review, 39(4), 814-834

Kashan, S., Shah, A., Ali, N., & Ali, Z. (2015). Journal for Studies in Management and Planning Declining Employee Performance in Public Sector Organizations: An Etiological Study of Public Sector Organizations in Pakistan. Retrieved from http://internationaljournalofresearch.org/index.php/JSMaP.

Krause, A. E., North, A. C., & Davidson, J. W. (2019). Using Self-Determination Theory to Examine Musical Participation and Well-Being. Frontiers in Psychology, 10. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2019.00405

Lameck, WU (2017). Decentralization and the Quality of Public Service Delivery in Tanzania. Groningen: Rijksuniversiteit Groningen.

Lehmann, L. (2016) Autonomy and work-life balance and their effects on job satisfaction (Unpublished Masters Thesis Utrecht University) retrieved from: https://dspace.library.uu.nl/handle/1874/337533

Malinowska, D., Tokarz, A., & Wardzichowska, A. (2018). Job autonomy in relation to work engagement and workaholism: Mediation of autonomous and controlled work motivation. International Journal of Occupational Medicine and Environmental Health, 31(4), 445–458.

Mboi, S. M. (2014). Factors influencing the performance of public servants in Kenya: a case of Machakos County. University of Nairobi. Retrieved from: http://erepository.uonbi.ac.ke/handle/11295/77112

Migliorini, L., Cardinali, P., & Rania, N. (2019). How Could Self-Determination Theory Be Useful for Facing Health Innovation Challenges? Frontiers in Psychology, 10. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2019.01870

Muecke, S., & Iseke, A. (2019). How Does Job Autonomy Influence Job Performance? A Meta-analytic Test of Theoretical Mechanisms. Academy of Management Proceedings, 2019(1), 14632. https://doi.org/10.5465/ambpp.2019.145

Mugenda, O. M., & Mugenda, A. G. (2012). Research Methods: Quantitative and Qualitative Approaches. Nairobi: Acts Press.

Naqvi, S. R., Kanwal, N., Ishtiaq, M., & Ali, M. (2013). Impact of job autonomy on organizational commitment: Moderating role of job satisfaction in Tobacco industry of Pakistan. Far East Journal of Psychology and Business, 12(5), 57-72.

Ngari, E., Muathe, S. & Kilika, J. (2018). Job Characteristics and Employee Performance in Private Equity Firms in Kenya. Journal of Business and Management.

Rizwan, M., Jamil, M. I., Shahid, U., Saeedi, A., Faisal, N., Ul Islam, Z., …Mateen, A. (2014). The Impact of the Job Stress, Job Autonomy and Working Conditions on Employee Satisfaction. International Journal of Human Resource Studies, 4(2).

Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2000). Self-determination theory and the facilitation of intrinsic motivation, social development, and well-being. American Psychologist, 55(1), 68–78. https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.55.1.68

Saragih, S. (2015). The Effects of Job Autonomy on Work Outcomes: Self Efficacy as An Intervening Variable. International Research Journal of Business Studies, 4(3). https://doi.org/10.21632/IRJBS.4.3.89

Schoonenboom, J., & Johnson, R. B. (2017). How to Construct a Mixed Methods Research Design. Kolner Zeitschrift fur Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie, 69(Suppl 2), 107–131. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11577-017-0454-1

Shobe, K. (2018). Productivity Driven by Job Satisfaction, Physical Work Environment, Management Support and Job Autonomy. Business and Economics Journal, 09(02). https://doi.org/10.4172/2151-6219.1000351

Sisodia, S., & Das, I. (2013). Effect of Job Autonomy Upon Organizational Commitment of Employees at Different Hierarchical Level. Psychological Thought, 6(2), 241-251. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.5964/psyct.v6i2.65

Suman, S. (2018) Poor Performance of Public Sector Enterprises (9 Causes. Retrieved from: http://www.economicsdiscussion.net/india/public-enterprises/poor-performance-of-public-sector-enterprises-9-causes/12889

Suteerawut, N. Vanno, V. & Khaikleng, P.(2016) Effects of Job Autonomy and Positive Psychological Capital on Job Performance of Banking Employees: Mediating Role of Intrinsic Work Motivation. ACP2016 Conference Proceedings. Retrieved from: https://papers.iafor.org/submission23174/

Vinney, C. (2019). What Is Self-Determination Theory? Retrieved January 30, 2020, from https://www.thoughtco.com/self-determination-theory-4628297

Wambui, L. M., Caroline Cherotich, B., Emily, T., & Dave, B. (2017). Effects of Work life Balance on Employees’ Performance in Institutions of Higher Learning. A Case Study of Kabarak University. Kabarak Journal of Research & Innovation, 4(2), 60–79. Retrieved from http://eserver.kabarak.ac.ke/ojs/

World Bank (2019). Kenya Devolution Support Project (P149129). Implementation Status & Results Report. World Bank

Zhou, Q., Li, Q. & Gong, S. (2019). "How Job Autonomy Promotes Employee’s Sustainable Development? A Moderated Mediation Model," Sustainability, MDPI, Open Access Journal, vol. 11(22), pages 1-14, November.

Creative Commons License

Copyright © 2016 - 2023. European Journal Of Social Sciences Studies  (ISSN 2501-8590) is a registered trademark of Open Access Publishing Group . All rights reserved.

This journal is a serial publication uniquely identified by an International Standard Serial Number ( ISSN ) serial number certificate issued by Romanian National Library. All the research works are uniquely identified by a  CrossRef   DOI  digital object identifier supplied by indexing and repository platforms. All the research works published on this journal are meeting the  Open Access Publishing  requirements and standards formulated by Budapest Open Access Initiative (2002), the  Bethesda Statement on Open Access Publishing (2003) and   Berlin Declaration on Open Access to Knowledge in the Sciences and Humanities (2003) and can be freely accessed, shared, modified, distributed and used in educational, commercial and non-commercial purposes under a  Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License . Copyrights of the published research works are retained by authors.

autonomy thesis pdf

IMAGES

  1. (PDF) Masters Thesis: WOMEN'S AUTONOMY AND UTILIZATION OF MATERNAL

    autonomy thesis pdf

  2. (PDF) The weak collective agential autonomy thesis

    autonomy thesis pdf

  3. Report Thesis Design For Autonomy LReichenfeld 4448103

    autonomy thesis pdf

  4. The Autonomy Thesis in Syntax

    autonomy thesis pdf

  5. (PDF) Autonomy

    autonomy thesis pdf

  6. (PDF) The Collective Moral Autonomy Thesis

    autonomy thesis pdf

VIDEO

  1. NixOS 94: Nix PhD Thesis Sections 4.3/4.4; Nix Language Semantics, Implementation

  2. Эссе о самих себе / Essays about themselves

  3. How to Download Thesis from Krishikosh(Updated 2024)

  4. Design and Control of a Miniature Autonomous Underwater Vehicle

  5. Self-Driving Cars

  6. Self Driving Car

COMMENTS

  1. PDF Understanding the Meaning of Autonomy

    The overall aim of this thesis was to understand the meaning of the phenomenon autonomy in learning, related to medicine and health -care students' perceptions of learning and development in clinical education. We know little about how autonomy influences individual thinking, action and awareness of learning in clinical education.

  2. PDF Understanding of the principle of Autonomy (Part 1)

    point of view, autonomy confers status, which implies that a person is owed respect, dignity and obligations.1,5 On legal grounds, autonomy separates personal concerns from the intrusion of the State, in so doing it preserves the sphere of personal sovereignty.2 At a personal level, autonomy is indicative of a self-creation process through

  3. The Relationship Between Remote Work and Job Satisfaction: The

    The Designated Thesis Committee Approves the Thesis Titled THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN REMOTE WORK AND JOB SATISFACTION: THE MEDIATING ROLES OF PERCEIVED AUTONOMY, WORK-FAMILY CONFLICT, AND TELECOMMUTING INTENSITY by Marie Antoinette Schall APPROVED FOR THE DEPARTMENT OF PSYCHOLOGY SAN JOSÉ STATE UNIVERSITY May 2019 Dr. Altovise Rogers

  4. (PDF) The Effects of Job Autonomy on Work Outcomes: Self Efficacy as an

    Therefore, job design. with high autonomy will be powerful in influence. employees' performance, satisfaction and reduce. job stress through increased self efficacy. Finally, by setting self ...

  5. PDF Learner Autonomy: a Case of M.ed. Students

    1.1.1.2 Learner Autonomy: A Complex and Ambiguous Concept 6 1.1.1.3 Learner Autonomy and Dominant Philosophies 8 1.1.2 Versions of Autonomy 9 1.1.3 Contexts for the Application of Autonomy 12 1.1.3.1 Autonomy Beyond the Classroom 12 1.1.3.2 Autonomy in the Classroom 13 1.1.4 Significance of Learner Autonomy 14 1.1.5 Fostering Autonomy 15

  6. PDF A pathway to learner autonomy: a self-determination theory ...

    Abstract. Concepts of learner autonomy and the self-determination theory provided a theoretical rationale for the action program for learner autonomy. The action pro-gram incorporated satisfying learners' basic psychologi-cal needs into English Foreign Language (EFL) course education. The action program was implemented for one academic year.

  7. Autonomy of English language learners: A scoping review of research and

    This study is a scoping review, which refers to a type of systematic literature review which summarizes substantive and methodological features of primary studies on a particular topic (Chong & Plonsky, 2021a; Visonà & Plonsky, 2019).A scoping review distinguishes itself from other types of research synthesis (e.g. narrative review) in terms of its more inclusive and systematic approach to ...

  8. PDF Learner Autonomy in Language Learning: Teachers' Beliefs

    understanding about learner autonomy and there was an alignment between teachers' beliefs and their actual teaching practices regarding learner autonomy, resulting in little evidence of learner autonomy found in any of the case study classrooms. The findings of this study will

  9. Autonomy in Moral and Political Philosophy

    Autonomy concerns the independence and authenticity of the desires (values, emotions, etc.) that move one to act in the first place. Some distinguish autonomy from freedom by insisting that freedom concerns particular acts while autonomy is a more global notion, referring to states of a person (Dworkin 1988, 13-15, 19-20).

  10. (PDF) Learner autonomy: A synthesis of theory and practice

    Introduction. Learner autonomy has been an important focus of educational practices and research for m ore than. three decades. The word autonomy is derived from auto-nomos, a Greek word (Voltz ...

  11. Understanding Autonomy: An Urgent Intervention

    This thesis is fundamentally at odds with an overwhelming consensus in contemporary bioethics that the principle of respect for autonomy, while important in everyday clinical encounters, must be 'curtailed', 'constrained', or 'overridden' by other principles in times of crisis.

  12. PDF Robust Ethics and the Autonomy Thesis

    the standard objections to the autonomy thesis; and (III) robust normative re-alism provides a better account of intrinsic value than any metaethical theory that identifies moral goodness with states of God. In this paper, I will argue Wielenberg's defense of the autonomy thesis fails. 3.

  13. (PDF) The Value-Free Ideals, the Authonomy Thesis, and ...

    PDF | Many debates about the role of non-epistemic values in science discuss the so-called Value-Free Ideal together with the Autonomy Thesis, to the... | Find, read and cite all the research you ...

  14. [PDF] Autonomy and the principle of respect for autonomy.

    The arguments of Immanuel Kant and John Stuart Mill concerning the principle of respect for autonomy are summarized as exemplars respectively of the deontological and utilitarian philosophical approaches. Autonomy is defined as the capacity to think, decide, and act freely and independently on the basis of such thought and decisions. Three types of autonomy are distinguished: autonomy of ...

  15. (PDF) The Autonomy Challenge: Examining the Pre-emption Thesis in

    Rescue Strategies for the Pre-emption Thesis 24 Having clarified the autonomy challenge, Postema claims the only way to maintain the pre-emption thesis as a suitable theoretical framework to explain the practical force of legal directives (including precedent) -in the context of the institutionalized autonomy theory, and as an element of the ...

  16. Why Value Autonomy?

    Abstract. This chapter discusses the value of autonomy as an intrinsic good. Autonomy presupposes the human ideal of a person with knowledge and agency—the freedom to make a choice, as well as the knowledge to select morally good choices from a variety of options. In this way, autonomy provides the grounds for liberalism, which argues against ...

  17. Syntactic change and the autonomy thesis

    Extract. I. Despite much activity, the recent attention paid by generativists to diachronic syntax has led to no significant implications for a general theory of grammar and, from a purely historical viewpoint, has failed to focus on any well-defined concepts of historical change. The papers in this field stand largely in isolation from each ...

  18. PDF Metaethics and the Autonomy of Morality

    domain.4 The autonomy of morality is thus the claim that: autonomy: Non-moral theses are irrelevant to the justifica-tion of normative ethical theories. I will sometimes refer to this as the autonomy thesis.5 The idea that nor-mative ethical theorizing is autonomous may appear intuitively attrac-tive.

  19. PDF Microsoft Word

    humanity and in turn a lack of the right to bodily autonomy. In this thesis I analyze the way in which Black people across genders and sexualities shape their bodily autonomy in response to witnessing police violence in the news and social media, Black Lives Matter protests, and Black people's own face-to-face encounters with police,

  20. (PDF) Examining the Interrelation Between Job Autonomy and Job

    Control Model (Karasek, 1979), job control can buffer the impact of job demands on the 140 strain and improve job satisfaction and well-being (Gameiro et al., 2020).

  21. Autonomy of Ethics

    thin concepts), the thesis that no inference from a premise or premises framed in nonmoral terms to a conclusion framed in thin moral terms is a priori valid is one well worth discussing. It wouldn't perhaps be, strictly speaking, an autonomy of ethics thesis; it would be an autonomy of a fragment of ethics thesis. But no great matter.

  22. Enabling tactical autonomy for unmanned surface vehicles in defensive

    The primary objective is to enable a swarm of defending vehicles to protect the HVU and successfully counter a swarm of aggressors with the ability to adapt to changing situations. This research makes it possible for autonomous defenders to react according to variables such as number of defenders, number of aggressors, known kinematic ...

  23. Reflections on personal autonomy

    One of the most intimate and problematic issues in philosophy is the matter of personal autonomy. It is intimate because most people care intensely about whether their decisions and way of life are autonomously chosen and lived. The issue of personal autonomy is problematic because the barriers to autonomous action can be subtle and unnoticeable. It is the thesis of this paper to discuss the ...

  24. Job Autonomy and Employee Performance in The County Government of

    The study found that there was a high job autonomy among employees in county government of Isiolo. Findings also showed as a high employee performance in the sample. There was a significant relationship (χ2 = 27.602, df = 16, p = 0.035) between job autonomy and employee performance.

  25. PDF stacks.stanford.edu

    stacks.stanford.edu