Encyclopedia Britannica

  • History & Society
  • Science & Tech
  • Biographies
  • Animals & Nature
  • Geography & Travel
  • Arts & Culture
  • Games & Quizzes
  • On This Day
  • One Good Fact
  • New Articles
  • Lifestyles & Social Issues
  • Philosophy & Religion
  • Politics, Law & Government
  • World History
  • Health & Medicine
  • Browse Biographies
  • Birds, Reptiles & Other Vertebrates
  • Bugs, Mollusks & Other Invertebrates
  • Environment
  • Fossils & Geologic Time
  • Entertainment & Pop Culture
  • Sports & Recreation
  • Visual Arts
  • Demystified
  • Image Galleries
  • Infographics
  • Top Questions
  • Britannica Kids
  • Saving Earth
  • Space Next 50
  • Student Center
  • Introduction
  • Types and expressions of rationalism
  • Epistemological rationalism in ancient philosophies
  • Epistemological rationalism in modern philosophies
  • Ethical rationalism

Expansion of religious rationalism

Four waves of religious rationalism, metaphysical.

  • Challenges to epistemological rationalism

Noam Chomsky

  • Who were Søren Kierkegaard’s parents?
  • Why is Søren Kierkegaard famous?
  • What was Noam Chomsky’s early life like?
  • How did Noam Chomsky influence the field of linguistics?
  • What are Noam Chomsky’s politics?

Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), German philosopher. Print published in London, 1812. Profile portrait surrounded by Ouroboros ancient Egyptian-Greek symbolic serpent with tail in mouth devouring itself representing unity of material and spiritual in eternal...

Religious rationalism

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

  • The Basics of Philosophy - Rationalism
  • University of Idaho - Dualism and Rationalism
  • Academia - Rationalism and the Justification of Knowledge in Rene Descartes
  • Rationalist Society of Australia - What is Rationalism?
  • Project MUSE - Rationalism in Greek Philosophy
  • University of Warwick - Rationalism and Empiricism
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Rationalism vs. Empiricism
  • Table Of Contents

Stirrings of religious rationalism were already felt in the Middle Ages regarding the Christian revelation . Thus, the skeptical mind of Peter Abelard (1079–1142) raised doubts by showing in his Sic et non (“Yes and No”) many contradictions among beliefs handed down as revealed truths by the Church Fathers . Aquinas , the greatest of the medieval thinkers, was a rationalist in the sense of believing that the larger part of revealed truth was intelligible to and demonstrable by reason , though he thought that a number of dogmas opaque to reason must be accepted on authority alone.

Religious rationalism did not come into its own, however, until the 16th and 17th centuries, when it took two chief forms: the scientific and the philosophical.

write an essay on rationalistic religion

Galileo was a pioneer in astronomy and the founder of modern dynamics . He conceived of nature as governed throughout by laws statable with mathematical precision; the book of nature, he said, is “written in mathematical form.” This notion not only ruled out the occasional appeal to miracle ; it also collided with dogmas regarding the permanent structure of the world—in particular with that which viewed the Earth as the motionless centre of the universe. When Galileo’s demonstration that the Earth moves around the Sun was confirmed by the work of Sir Isaac Newton (1642–1727) and others, a battle was won that marked a turning point in the history of rationalism, since it provided a decisive victory in a crucial case of conflict between reason and apparently revealed truth.

The rationalism of Descartes, as already shown, was the outcome of philosophical doubt rather than of scientific inquiry. The self-evidence of the cogito , seen by his “natural light,” he made the ideal for all other knowledge. The uneasiness that the church soon felt in the face of such a test was not unfounded, for Descartes was in effect exalting the natural light into the supreme court even in the field of religion. He argued that the guarantee against the possibility that even this natural light might be deceptive lay in the goodness of the Creator. But then to prove this Creator, he had to assume the prior validity of the natural light itself. Logically, therefore, the last word lay with rational insight, not with any outside divine warrant ( see Cartesian circle ). Descartes was inadvertently beginning a Copernican revolution in theology . Before his time, the truths regarded as most certain were those accepted from revelation; afterward these truths were subject to the judgment of human reason, thus breaking the hold of authority on the European mind.

a classroom in Brazil

The rationalist attitude quickly spread, its advance forming several waves of general interest and influence. The first wave occurred in England in the form of Deism . Deists accepted the existence of God but spurned supernatural revelation. The earliest member of this school, Lord Herbert of Cherbury (1583–1648), held that a just God would not reveal himself to a part of his creation only and that the true religion is thus a universal one, which achieves its knowledge of God through common reason. The Deistic philosopher John Toland (1670–1722), in his Christianity Not Mysterious (1696), sought to show that “there is nothing in the Gospels contrary to reason, nor above it”; any doctrine that is really above reason would be meaningless to humans. Attacking revelation, the freethinking polemicist Anthony Collins (1676–1729) maintained that the prophecies of the Hebrew Bible (Old Testament) failed of fulfillment; and the religious controversialist Thomas Woolston (1670–1733) urged that the New Testament miracles, as recorded, are incredible. Matthew Tindal (1657–1733), most learned of the English Deists, argued that the essential part of Christianity is its ethics , which, being clearly apparent to natural reason, leaves revelation superfluous. Thus the Deists, professing for the most part to be religious themselves, did much to reconcile their public to the free play of ideas in religion.

write an essay on rationalistic religion

The second wave of religious rationalism, less moderate in tone and consequences, was French. This wave, reflecting an engagement with the problem of natural evil , involved a decay in the natural theology of Deism such that it merged eventually with the stream that led to materialistic atheism . Its moving spirit was Voltaire (1694–1778), who had been impressed by some of the Deists during a stay in England . Like them, he thought that a rational person would believe in God but not in supernatural inspiration. Hardly a profound philosopher, he was a brilliant journalist, clever and humorous in argument , devastating in satire, and warm in human sympathies. In his Candide and in many other writings, he poured irreverent ridicule on the Christian scheme of salvation as incoherent and on the church hierarchy as cruel and oppressive. In these attitudes he had the support of Denis Diderot (1713–84), editor of the most widely read encyclopaedia that had appeared in Europe . The rationalism of these thinkers and their followers, directed against both the religious and the political traditions of their time, did much to prepare the ground for the explosive French Revolution .

The next wave of religious rationalism occurred in Germany under the influence of Hegel , who held that a religious creed is a halfway house on the road to a mature philosophy , the product of a reason that is still under the sway of feeling and imagination. This idea was taken up and applied with learning and acuteness to the origins of Christianity by David Friedrich Strauss (1808–74), who published in 1835, at the age of 27, a remarkable and influential three-volume work, Das Leben Jesu ( The Life of Jesus, Critically Examined , 1846). Relying largely on internal inconsistencies in the Synoptic Gospels , Strauss undertook to prove these books to be unacceptable as revelation and unsatisfactory as history. He then sought to show how an imaginative people innocent of either history or science, convinced that a messiah would appear, and deeply moved by a unique moral genius, inevitably wove myths about his birth and death, his miracles, and his divine communings.

Strauss’s thought as it affected religion was continued by the philosophical historian Ernest Renan (1823–92) and as it affected philosophy by the humanist Ludwig Feuerbach (1804–72) of the Hegelian left. Renan’s Vie de Jésus (1863; Life of Jesus ) did for France what Strauss’s book had done for Germany, though the two differed greatly in character. Whereas Strauss’s work had been an intellectual exercise in destructive criticism , Renan’s was an attempt to reconstruct the mind of Jesus as a wholly human person—a feat of imagination, performed with a disarming admiration and even reverence for its subject and with a felicity of style that gave it a large and lasting audience. Feuerbach’s Wesen des Christentums (1841; Essence of Christianity ) applied the myth theory even to belief in the existence of God, holding that “man makes God in his own image.”

The fourth wave occurred in Victorian England, following the publication in 1859 of Origin of Species by Charles Darwin (1809–82). This book was taken as a challenge to the authority of Scripture because there was a clear inconsistency between the Genesis account of creation and the biological account of humans’ slow emergence from lower forms of life. The battle raged with bitterness for several decades but died away as the theory of evolution gained more general acceptance.

Status of rationalism

With increasing freedom of thought and wider acceptance of scientific views, rationalism in religion lost its novelty and much of its controversial excitement. To the contemporary mind, it is too obvious to warrant debate that reason and revelation cannot both qualify as sources of ultimate truth, for, were they to conflict, truth itself would become self-contradictory. Hence theologians sought accommodation through new interpretative principles that discern different grades of authenticity within the Scriptures and through new views of religious truth, existential rather than cognitive , that turn from propositional dogmas to the explication of lived human existence . Criticism of supernaturalism, however, was still carried on by such societies as the Rationalist Press Association, in Great Britain, and the Humanist Association, in the United States .

Rationalism in ethics suffered its share of criticism. Regarding its lists of rules—on the keeping of promises, the return of loaned goods, etc.—it was argued, for example, that if they were specific enough to be useful (as in the rule against lying or stealing), they would tend to have exceptions—which no rule laid down by reason ought to have. On the other hand, if without exceptions, they would often prove to be tautologies : the rule of justice , for example, that one should give all persons their due, would then mean only that one should give them what is justly theirs. After enduring a period of eclipse, however, during which noncognitive theories of ethics ( emotive and existential) and relativism had preempted the field, rationalistic views, which agree in holding that moral standards do not depend upon the varying attitudes of persons or peoples, received renewed attention in the mid-20th century. Prominent among these developments was the “ good-reasons ” approach taken by the broadly gauged scholar Stephen Toulmin (1922–2009), the contemporary philosopher Kurt Baier, and others, which examined the contexts of various moral situations and explored the kinds of justification appropriate for each.

write an essay on rationalistic religion

Typical of the ways of reasoning employed by rationalists were two approaches taken to the metaphysical doctrine that all things are connected by internal relations : one a logical, the other a causal argument. An internal relation is one that could not be removed without affecting the terms themselves between which the relation holds. The argument runs: Everything is related to everything else at least by the relation “A is different from B.” But difference is itself an internal relation, since the terms could not remain the same if it were removed. Hence everything is so connected with everything else that it could not be what it is unless they were what they are. The appeal to internal relations played an important part in the philosophies of Hegel, F.H. Bradley , and A.N. Whitehead (1861–1947).

The other line of argument is causal . Every event, it is maintained, is connected with every other, either directly or indirectly. Sir James Jeans (1877–1946), an astrophysicist and popularizer of science, argued that if the law of gravitation is valid, people cannot crook their little fingers without affecting the fixed stars. Here the causal relation is direct. It can also be shown that seemingly unrelated events are joined indirectly through their common connection with some remote historical event, by a chain of events leading back, for example, to Columbus ’s landing on the North American continent. But if this had been different, all its consequences would presumably have been different; thus, an indirect and internal relation proves to have been present.

Many rationalists held with Spinoza that the causal relation is really a logical one—that a causal law, if precisely stated, would reveal a connection in which the character of the cause logically necessitates that of its effect; and if this is true, they maintained, the facts and events of the world must thus compose a single rational and intelligible order.

In the 20th century, such rationalism met with a new and unexpected difficulty presented by quantum mechanics . According to the indeterminacy principle , formulated in 1927 by the German physicist Werner Heisenberg (1901–76), it is impossible to discover with precision both the position and the velocity of a moving electron at the same time. This implies that definite causal laws for the behaviour of these particles can never be attained, but only statistical laws governing the behaviour of immense aggregates of them. Causality, and with it the possibility of rational understanding, seemed to be suspended in the subatomic world. Some interpreters of the new physics, however, notably Max Planck (1858–1947), Albert Einstein (1879–1955), and Bertrand Russell (1872–1970), sustained the hopes of the rationalists by insisting that what was excluded by the indeterminacy principle was not the fact of causality in this realm but only the precise knowledge of it.

Indeed, some leaders of 20th-century science took the new developments in physics as on the whole supporting rationalism. Protons and electrons, they contended, though beyond the reach of the senses, can still be known, and their behaviour, at least in groups, is increasingly found to conform to mathematical law. In 1932 Jeans said, with a curious echo of Galileo, “The universe appears to have been designed by a pure mathematician.”

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

"The Idea of a Rationalistic Philosophy of Religion and Its Challenges" in God as Reason: Essays in Philosophical Theology. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2013

Profile image of Vittorio G Hosle

Related Papers

Vittorio G Hosle

write an essay on rationalistic religion

Studies in Religion

Andrew C Stout

Kadivedu Joshua Samuel

The title religious scholar, it has to be remembered, is a very ambiguous categorization. It could either mean those who are engaged in academic work in the religious department of a University or it could also include those involved in subjective religious study, like in a seminary. From a critical post-modern perspective, it could also include along with the academics, not only religious leaders (as scholars in terms of their acquired knowledge and their experiences) but also religious believers who profess and practice their religious beliefs in relevance to the needs of their situations. However, in this paper I want to approach this category from an academic perspective. Though the term could also include theology, I cannot help noticing the fact that this category-religious scholar-is generally used to refer to religionists 1 in a 'secular' public education system. This indirectly implies that to be a 'religious scholar' one has to be objective by maintaining a safe distance from the theological space. In other words, scholarship is to be seen as an objective exercise, that can be done (only) by the 'secular' person (who is an outsider to the religious space). What does this mean for theology in general and comparative theology in particular? What does this mean for the communities whose religious beliefs are (claimed to be) objectively studied? It is with these questions that I begin this brief paper on religious scholarship. The intention of this paper is to identify what religion and religious study is really about and the problems involved in the construction of the category of religion as we understand it today. Based on this, I intend to propose an alternative way of perceiving religious scholarship that is both unhegemonic and relevant for important issues today. 2 The Evolution of the Religious scholar Religion as we understand it today, contrary to our general assumption, is neither a sui generis category nor was it present for ever in human history. Of course, there were different manifestations of religious beliefs throughout human history. But the question is whether, religion was the same as we experience it today. Thanks to the postcolonial scholars, who have alerted us to the fact that religion is not a permanent essentialized category. Brent Nongbri has shown that religion certainly is a conglomeration of different historical events. He systematically argues that in the context of Protestantism, colonialism and enlightenment, religion had to be carefully separated by the Europeans from the public space in order to strategically maintain the stability of the global society PAGE 5 1 I use the word 'religionist' as used by John Thatamanil. He uses it for the scholars who are involved in a secular study of religion. However, as he notices, the usage of the term is not without ambiguity. John J. Thatamanil, " Managing Multiple Religious and Scholarly Identities: An Argument for a Theological Study of Hinduism " , in

Theological Studies

joseph dinoia

shah jubaer

This research paper is a well-structured arrangement for the understudies who have as of now done an introductory course in philosophy. Each article on "philosophy of religion" presents a centre common subject in contemporary philosophy and offers understudies an available but considerable transition from basic to higher-level academic work in that subject. The arrangement is accessible to non-specialists, and each segment spurs and elucidates the problems and positions presented. An orientating title briefly presents its topic and reminds users of any vital fabric they ought to have held from a commonplace initial course. A significant consideration is given to explaining the central philosophical issues of a subject and the most competing solutions and arguments for those arrangements. The essential point of this research article is to educate understudies within the fundamental problems, positions, and contentions of modern reasoning instead of convincing understudies of a single position. The presumption which underlies this trust is that total non-partisanship in reasoning is not one or the other conceivable nor alluring. Philosophical work continuously reflects as per Philosophy of Religion and most profound commitments. Such commitments, be that as it may, don't block an honest to goodness endeavouring for basic trustworthiness.

Nederduitse Gereformeerde Teologiese Tydskrif

Mikael Stenmark

George Karuvelil

Convinced that those who fail to learn from history are doomed<br> to repeat it, this paper looks at the history of the interaction between<br> Christian faith and culture in the Western tradition. Presenting two<br> millennia of history in such limited space is bound to be fragmentary.<br> But it serves the limited purpose of uncovering the dynamics of the<br> interaction between faith and culture. It is seen that faith flourished as <br> long as it remained faithful to this dynamics and it declined when it<br> failed to do so, i.e., from the modem period to the present. The latter can<br> be seen as a failure of wisdom inasmuch as wisdom consists in creatively<br> responding to a given situation. This realization, in turn, prompts another<br> look at Aquinas to see if he can function as an exemplar for integrating<br> reason and faith in the contemporary world.<br>

Dr. Javad Taheri

This paper aimed to present a novel approach to the comparative philosophy of religion which I call traditions-oriented. It is related to and yet distinct from both comparative philosophy and confessional (tradition-oriented) comparative theology. This paper begins with a reflection on the meaning and employment of ‘comparison’ in the context of philosophical analysis. What follows is an analysis of the nature of the comparative practice conducted under the umbrella concept of the comparative philosophy of religion. After sketching out the developmental trajectory of research through which a traditions-oriented, non-neutral, comparative philosophy of religion can emerge, the articulation and implementation of a global monotheistic philosophy of religion is suggested. Two case-studies from the area of Muslim-Christian comparative reflection are used to demonstrate the effectiveness of the approach developed in this paper.

Faith, Reason, and Theosis

Aristotle Papanikolaou

Mary Catherine Hilkert

Loading Preview

Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.

RELATED PAPERS

Anh Dao Tran

HTS Teologiese Studies / Theological Studies

Jaco Beyers

Zachary Porcu

Rik Van Nieuwenhove

Immanuel Kant

Ivan Strenski

Religious Studies

Thomas D Carroll

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Richard Amesbury

Wojciech Grygiel

C. Markschies, Y. Friedmann (eds.), Religious Polemics

Johannes Zachhuber

Daniel Varadi

Comity and the Grace of Method

Herman Tull

Rationalisations in Religion: Judaism, Christianity, and Islam

Irish Theological Quarterly

William J. Abraham

Miri Fenton

The Heythrop Journal

Anthony Carroll

Sergey Astapov

Journal of the American Academy of …

Hugh Nicholson

Ankur Barua

Philosophia: International Journal of Philosophy

Jove Jim S Aguas

Thomson Wadsworth

Abhivaykti Shah

Svensk Teologisk Kvartalskrift

Elena Namli

The rationality of faith and the benefits of religion

  • Published: 13 January 2017
  • Volume 81 , pages 213–227, ( 2017 )

Cite this article

write an essay on rationalistic religion

  • Brian Ballard 1  

1624 Accesses

5 Citations

Explore all metrics

Religions don’t simply make claims about the world; they also offer existential resources, resources for dealing with basic human problems, such as the need for meaning, love, identity, and personal growth. For instance, a Buddhist’s resources for addressing these existential needs are different than a Christian’s. Now, imagine someone who is agnostic but who is deciding whether to put faith in religion A or religion B. Suppose she thinks A and B are evidentially on par, but she regards A as offering much more by way of existential resources. Is it epistemically rational for her to put her faith in A rather than B on this basis? It is natural to answer No. After all, what do the existential resources of a religion have to do with its truth? However, I argue that this attitude is mistaken. My thesis is that the extent to which it is good for a certain religion to be true is relevant to the epistemic (rather than merely pragmatic) rationality of faith in that religion. This is plausible, I’ll argue, on the correct account of the nature of faith, including the ways that emotion and desire can figure into faith and contribute to its epistemic rationality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save.

  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime

Price includes VAT (Russian Federation)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Rent this article via DeepDyve

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

write an essay on rationalistic religion

Faith and Reason: an Alternative Gandhian Understanding

Desiderata for rational, non-doxastic faith.

write an essay on rationalistic religion

Faith, Philosophy and the Elemental

http://islamicpamphlets.com/why-islam-the-beauty-and-benefits-of-islam .

From a speech at Prestonwood Baptist Church in Plano, TX, November 18, 2010.

It is hard to define ‘religion’, but Yandell ( 1990 ) does a pretty good job: “a conceptual system that provides an interpretation of the world and the place of human beings in it, that rests on that interpretation an account of how life should be lived … and that expresses this interpretation in a set of practices”; quoted in Audi ( 2008 , p. 93). This is at least a useful heuristic (even though it would include some forms of atheism as a religion).

What I’m defending here is reminiscent of Pascal’s wager, as well as James ( 1897 ). However, the major difference is that Pascal’s wager doesn’t seem to have much to do with epistemic rationality, and it isn’t clear whether James’ view does either. In a similar vein, Rota ( 2016 ) and Williams ( 2011 ) argue that the value of a religion for human life can provide non-epistemic reasons that may combine with epistemic reasons to make faith all-things-considered rational. In contrast, my view is that the value of a religion can itself provide epistemic reason to have faith. What I’m defending here is also reminiscent of moral arguments for the existence of God according to which theistic faith provides moral benefits (Adams 1995 ; Zagzebski 1984 ). But don’t confuse my view with these either. My view is strictly concerned with the extent to which such moral and pragmatic benefits can themselves make it epistemically rational to have faith. In this sense, my view more closely resembles Pace ( 2010 ), although Pace claims that moral-pragmatic considerations are relevant to the epistemic rationality of belief , while I am interested in faith, which may or may not require belief. Finally, Audi ( 2011 , p. 67), notes briefly that the epistemic status of faith’s evaluative component partly determines the epistemic status of faith itself. I take myself to be offering a full-fledged account of this claim.

Of course, some have already made important progress here, such as Adams ( 1999 ), Flanagan ( 2011 ), Roberts ( 2007 ), Stump ( 2010 ), and Williams ( 2011 ).

Many endorse the claim that faith requires positive evaluation of the faith object. See Howard-Snyder ( 2013 , p. 360), who offers illustrative passages from Adams ( 1995 ), Alston ( 1996 ), and Audi ( 2008 ), all of whom endorse some evaluative condition on faith. For an account that rejects the evaluative condition on faith, see Dougherty ( 2014 ).

Of course, some metaethical non-cognitivists deny that we have evaluative beliefs to begin with. Nevertheless, other non-cognitivists allow that we have evaluative beliefs, and such non-cognitivists tend to adopt a minimalism or quasi-realism that would equally allow that evaluative beliefs are epistemically assessable.

Some philosophers, such as Solomon ( 1976 ), hold that emotions are evaluative beliefs. But we should reject this view because we can have emotions that conflict with our evaluative beliefs, as when you fear the rodent you believe to be harmless. Now, you might respond that in all such cases what we have are two conflicting evaluative beliefs. But that seems to attribute way too much irrationality to such cases.

See Green ( 1992 ) and Marks ( 1982 ) for the view that emotions are reducible to belief-desire couplings. For criticism see Griffiths ( 1997 , Ch. 2), and Deonna and Teroni ( 2012 , Ch. 3).

By ‘pragmatic rationality’ I mean rationality in light of the goal of maximizing pragmatic benefits. Something like ‘prudential’ or ‘economic’ rationality might have done just as well.

This conception of the epistemic goal is sometimes invoked in the faith literature, as in McKaughan ( 2016 , Sect. V). Of course, not everyone holds this view of the epistemic goal. There is a recent movement claiming that the epistemic goal is towards understanding rather than true belief (e.g., Kvanvig 2003 ). Would this imply that the epistemic rationality of faith hangs on whether faith deepens or in some way improves understanding, casting a new light on the old adage of “faith seeking understanding”? This is extremely interesting but I cannot discuss it further here.

I do not assume here that direct, perceptual evidence is always better than testimony. The point is rather that it is better to veridically perceive p than to hallucinate not-p, even if in both cases one has a true belief that-p or even knows that-p. Thanks to Duncan Pritchard and an anonymous referee for discussion on this issue.

This view of the epistemic goal also helps with the old problem of how some false scientific theories better approximate the truth than other false theories do. Representational success is, after all, a degreed notion, like accuracy , while truth is, most think, strictly binary.

This case might tempt certain counterexamples. Note, however, that for my purposes I am not, and need not be, offering a sufficient condition for a state’s being assessable for epistemic rationality.

For the view that emotions are evaluative beliefs, judgments, or some cognitive state in the vicinity, see Foot ( 1978a , 1978b ), Greenspan ( 1988 ), Helm ( 2001 ), Kenny ( 1963 ), Lazarus ( 1991 ), Lyons ( 1980 ), Neu ( 1977 ), Nussbaum ( 2001 ), and Solomon ( 1976 ). For the view that emotions are evaluative perceptions or perception-like states with evaluative content, see Dancy ( 2014 ), Döring ( 2003 ), McDowell ( 1979 , 1985 ), Prinz ( 2004 ), Roberts ( 2003 ), and Tappolet ( 2012 ). For the view that emotions are sui generis experiences with evaluative content, see Johnston ( 2002 ), Mendelovici ( 2014 ), and Tye ( 2008 ). For recent criticism of the thesis that emotions have evaluative representational content, see Deonna and Teroni ( 2012 ).

But for an alternative explanation, see Deonna and Teroni ( 2014 ).

I’m not claiming that any state that is representational is thereby assessable for epistemic rationality. For instance, it is typically held that visual states are representational but not assessable for epistemic rationality (for an exception, see Siegel 2017 ). The representational content of emotion is just part of the explanation as to why it can be assessed for epistemic rationality.

I’m just assuming justification is not factive (contra Littlejohn 2014 ).

It’s worth contrasting this with Wainwright ( 1995 ), who articulates a different account of how emotions or desires are relevant to the rationality of (Christian) faith. He argues that certain affective or conative dispositions are required in order to properly assess the epistemic reasons one has for theistic belief. In contrast, I am arguing that affective or conative states can themselves be epistemically rational, and so directly contribute to the epistemic status of the faith they constitute.

See Williams ( 2011 , Ch. 1), for more sustained discussion of what our existential needs are (albeit from a Christian point of view).

Adams, R. (1995). Moral faith. Journal of Philosophy, 92 (2), 75–95.

Article   Google Scholar  

Adams, M. (1999). Horrendous evils and the goodness of god . Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Google Scholar  

Alston, W. (1996). Belief, acceptance, and religious faith. In J. Jordon & D. Howard-Snyder (Eds.), Faith, freedom, and rationality . Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

Audi, R. (2008). Belief, faith, and acceptance. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 63 (1), 87–102.

Audi, R. (2011). Rationality and religious commitment . New York: Oxford University Press.

Book   Google Scholar  

Buchak, L. (2012). Can it be rational to have faith? In J. Chandler & V. Harrison (Eds.), Probability in the philosophy of religion . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

D’Arms, J., & Jacobson, D. (2000). The moralistic fallacy: On the ‘appropriateness’ of emotions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61 (1), 65–90.

Dancy, J. (2014). Intuition and emotion. Ethics, 124 (4), 787–812.

Deonna, J., & Teroni, F. (2012). The emotions . New York: Routledge.

Deonna, J., & Teroni, F. (2014). In what sense are emotions evaluations? In C. Todd & S. Roeser (Eds.), Emotion and value . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Döring, S. A. (2003). Explaining action by emotion. Philosophical Quarterly, 53 (211), 214–230.

Dougherty, T. (2014). Faith, trust, and testimony. In T. O’Connor & L. F. Goins (Eds.), Intellectual virtue and religious faith . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Flanagan, O. (2011). The bodhisattva’s brain . Cambridge, MA: MIT.

Foley, R. (1991). Rationality, belief and commitment. Synthese, 89 (3), 365–392.

Foot, P. (1978a). Hume’s theory of moral judgment. In Virtues and vices and other essays in moral philosophy . Berkeley: University of California Press.

Foot, P. (1978b). Moral beliefs. In Virtues and vices and other essays in moral philosophy . Berkeley: University of California Press.

Green, O. H. (1992). The emotions . Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Greenspan, P. (1988). Emotions and reasons . New York: Routledge.

Griffiths, P. (1997). What emotions really are . Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Hall, S. (2003). Is buddhism good for your health? The New York Times . Retrieved November 28, 2016, from http://www.nytimes.com/2003/09/14/magazine/is-buddhism-good-for-your-health.html .

Helm, B. (2001). Emotional reason: Deliberation, motivation, and the nature of value . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Hitchens, C. (2007). God is not great . New York: Hackette Book Group Inc.

Howard-Snyder, D. (2013). Propositional faith: What it is and what it is not. American Philosophical Quarterly, 50 (4), 357–372.

Jacoby, S. (2013). The blessings of atheism. The New York Times . Retrieved November 28, 2016, from http://www.nytimes.com/2013/01/06/opinion/sunday/the-blessings-of-atheism.html .

James, W. (1897). The will to believe and other essays . London: Longmans, Green, and Co.

Johnston, M. (2002). The authority of affect. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63 (1), 181–214.

Kenny, A. (1963). Emotion, action, and will . London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Kvanvig, J. (2003). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Lazarus, R. (1991). Emotion and adaptation . New York: Oxford University Press.

Littlejohn, C. (2014). Justification and the truth connection . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Lyons, W. E. (1980). Emotion . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Marks, J. (1982). A theory of emotion. Philosophical Studies, 42 (1), 227–242.

McDowell, J. (1979). Virtue and reason. The Monist, 62 (3), 331–350.

McDowell, J. (1985). Value and secondary qualities. In T. Honderich (Ed.), Morality and objectivity . London: Routledge.

McKaughan, D. (2016). Action-centered faith, doubt, and rationality. Journal of Philosophical Research, 41 (Supplement), 71–90.

Mendelovici, A. (2014). Pure intentionalism about moods and emotions. In U. Kriegel (Ed.), Current controversies in philosophy of mind . London: Routledge.

Neu, J. (1977). Emotion, thought, and therapy . Berkeley: University of California Press.

Nussbaum, M. (2001). Upheavals of thought: The intelligence of emotion . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Oddie, G. (2005). Value, reality, and desire . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Pace, M. (2010). The epistemic value of moral considerations: Justification, moral encroachment, and James’ ‘will to believe’. Nous, 45 (2), 239–268.

Prinz, J. (2004). Gut reactions: A perceptual theory of emotion . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Roberts, R. C. (2003). Emotions . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Roberts, R. C. (2007). Spiritual emotions . Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co.

Rota, M. (2016). Taking pascal’s wager: Faith, evidence, and the abundant life . Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.

Schafer, K. (2013). Perception and the rational force of desire. Journal of Philosophy, 110 (5), 258–281.

Scheffler, S. (2010). Equality and tradition . New York: Oxford University Press.

Siegel, S. (2017). The rationality of perception . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Solomon, R. C. (1976). The passions . Garden City, NY: Anchor Books.

Stampe, D. (1987). The authority of desire. Philosophical Review, 96 (3), 335–381.

Stump, E. (2010). Wandering in darkness . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Tappolet, C. (2012). Emotions, perceptions, and emotional illusions. In C. Clotilde (Ed.), Perceptual illusions: Philosophical and psychological essays . Basingstoke: Palgrave-Macmillan.

Tye, M. (2008). The experience of emotion: An intentionalist theory. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 243 (1), 25–50.

Vahid, H. (2010). Rationalizing belief: Evidential vs. pragmatic reasons. Synthese, 176 (3), 447–462.

Wainwright, W. (1995). Reason and the heart . Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Williams, C. (2011). Existential reasons for belief in god . Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.

Yandell, K. (1990). The nature of faith: Religious, monotheistic, and Christian. Faith and Philosophy, 7 (4), 451–469.

Zagzebski, L. (1984). Does ethics need god? Faith and Philosophy, 4 (3), 294–303.

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Department of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 1001 Cathedral of Learning, Pittsburgh, PA, 15260, USA

Brian Ballard

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brian Ballard .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Ballard, B. The rationality of faith and the benefits of religion. Int J Philos Relig 81 , 213–227 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-016-9599-5

Download citation

Received : 28 November 2016

Accepted : 03 December 2016

Published : 13 January 2017

Issue Date : April 2017

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-016-9599-5

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Rationality
  • Find a journal
  • Publish with us
  • Track your research

W

  • General Philosophy
  • Continental Philosophy

write an essay on rationalistic religion

Religion and Rationality: Essays on Reason, God and Modernity

ISBN: 978-0-745-62486-0

write an essay on rationalistic religion

Jürgen Habermas , Eduardo Mendieta

In a new introduction written especially for this volume, Eduardo Mendieta places Habermas' engagement with religion in the context of his work as a whole. Mendieta also discusses Habermas' writings in relation to Jewish Messianism and the Frankfurt School, showing how the essays in Religion and Rationality , one of which is translated into English for the first time, foreground an important, yet often neglected, dimension of critical theory. The volume concludes with an original extended interview, also in English for the first time, in which Habermas develops his current views on religion in modern society.

This book will be of great interest to students and scholars in theology, religious studies and philosophy, as well as to all those already familiar with Habermas' work.

2. The first book to bring together Habermas's key writings on religion.

3. Includes an original interview with Habermas, as well as an introduction written especially for the volume.

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Rationalism vs. Empiricism

In its most general terms, the dispute between rationalism and empiricism has been taken to concern the extent to which we are dependent upon experience in our effort to gain knowledge of the external world. It is common to think of experience itself as being of two kinds: sense experience, involving our five world-oriented senses, and reflective experience, including conscious awareness of our mental operations. The distinction between the two is drawn primarily by reference to their objects: sense experience allows us to acquire knowledge of external objects, whereas our awareness of our mental operations is responsible for the acquisition of knowledge of our minds. In the dispute between rationalism and empiricism, this distinction is often neglected; rationalist critiques of empiricism usually contend that the latter claims that all our ideas originate with sense experience.

It is generally agreed that most rationalists claim that there are significant ways in which our concepts and knowledge are gained independently of sense experience. To be a rationalist, however, does not require one to claim that our knowledge is acquired independently of any experience: at its core, the Cartesian Cogito depends on our reflective, intuitive awareness of the existence of occurrent thought. Rationalists generally develop their view in two steps. First, they argue that there are cases where the content of our concepts or knowledge outstrips the information that sense experience can provide. Second, they construct accounts of how reason, in some form or other, provides that additional information about the external world.

Most empiricists present complementary lines of thought. First, they develop accounts of how experience alone -- sense experience, reflective experience, or a combination of the two -- provides the information that rationalists cite, insofar as we have it in the first place. Second, while empiricists attack the rationalists’ accounts of how reason is a primary source of concepts or knowledge, they show that reflective understanding can and usually does supply some of the missing links (famously, Locke believed that our idea of substance, in general, is a composite idea, incorporating elements derived from both sensation and reflection, e.g. Essay, 2.23.2).

The distinction between rationalism and empiricism is not without problems. One of the main issues is that almost no author falls neatly into one camp or another: it has been argued that Descartes, for instance, who is commonly regarded as a representative rationalist (at least with regard to metaphysics), had clear empiricist leanings (primarily with regard to natural philosophy, where sense experience plays a crucial role, according to Clarke 1982). Conversely, Locke, who is thought to be a paradigmatic empiricist, argued that reason is on equal footing with experience, when it comes to the knowledge of certain things, most famously of moral truths ( Essay, 4.3.18). In what follows, we clarify what this distinction has traditionally been taken to apply to, as well as point out its (by now) widely-recognized shortcomings.

1.1 Rationalism

1.2 empiricism, 2. the intuition/deduction thesis, 3. the innate knowledge thesis, 4. the innate concept thesis, other internet resources, related entries, 1. introduction.

The dispute between rationalism and empiricism takes place primarily within epistemology, the branch of philosophy devoted to studying the nature, sources, and limits of knowledge. Knowledge itself can be of many different things and is usually divided among three main categories: knowledge of the external world, knowledge of the internal world or self-knowledge, and knowledge of moral and/or aesthetical values. We may find that there are category-specific conditions that must be satisfied for knowledge to occur and that it is easier or more difficult to shape certain questions and answers, depending on whether we focus on the external world or on the values. However, some of the defining questions of general epistemology include the following.

What is the nature of propositional knowledge, knowledge that a particular proposition about the world, ourselves, morality, or beauty is true?

To know a proposition, we must believe it and it must be true, but something more is required, something that distinguishes knowledge from a lucky guess. Let’s call this additional element ‘warrant’. A good deal of philosophical work has been invested in trying to determine the nature of warrant.

How can we gain knowledge?

We can form true beliefs just by making lucky guesses. How to gain warranted beliefs is less clear. Moreover, to know the external world or anything about beauty, for instance, we must be able to think about the external world or about beauty, and it is unclear how we gain the concepts we use in thought or what assurance, if any, we have that the ways in which we divide up the world using our concepts correspond to divisions that actually exist.

What are the limits of our knowledge?

Some aspects of the external world, ourselves, or the moral and aesthetical values may be within the limits of our thought but beyond the limits of our knowledge; faced with competing descriptions of them, we cannot know which description is true. Some aspects of the external world, ourselves, or the moral and aesthetical values may even be beyond the limits of our thought, so that we cannot form intelligible descriptions of them, let alone know that a particular description is true.

The disagreement between rationalism and empiricism primarily concerns the second question, regarding the sources of our concepts and knowledge. In some instances, the disagreement on this topic results in conflicting responses to the other questions as well. The disagreement may extend to incorporate the nature of warrant or where the limits of our thought and knowledge are. Our focus here will be on the competing rationalist and empiricist responses to the second question.

There are three main theses that are usually seen as relevant for drawing the distinction between rationalism and empiricism, with a focus on the second question. While the first thesis has been traditionally seen as distinguishing between rationalism and empiricism, scholars now mostly agree that most rationalists and empiricists abide by the so-called Intuition/Deduction thesis , concerning the ways in which we become warranted in believing propositions in a particular subject area.

The Intuition/Deduction Thesis : Some propositions in a particular subject area, S, are knowable by us by intuition alone; still others are knowable by being deduced from intuited propositions.

Intuition is a form of direct, immediate insight. Intuition has been likened to (a sort of internal) perception by most rationalists and empiricists alike. Intellectually grasping a proposition, we just “see” it to be true in such a way as to form a true, warranted belief in it. (As discussed in Section 2 below, the nature of this intellectual “seeing” needs explanation.) Deduction is a process in which we derive conclusions from intuited premises through valid arguments, ones in which the conclusion must be true if the premises are true. We intuit, for example, that the number three is prime and that it is greater than two. We then deduce from this knowledge that there is a prime number greater than two. Intuition and deduction thus provide us with knowledge that is independent, for its justification, of experience. This type of knowledge, since Kant, is commonly called “ a priori ”.

We can generate different versions of the Intuition/Deduction thesis by substituting different subject areas for the variable ‘S’. Several rationalists and empiricists take mathematics to be knowable by intuition and deduction. Some place ethical truths in this category. Some include metaphysical claims, such as that God exists, we have free will, and our mind and body are distinct substances.

The second thesis that is relevant to the distinction between rationalism and empiricism is the Innate Knowledge thesis .

The Innate Knowledge Thesis : We have knowledge of some truths in a particular subject area, S, as part of our nature.

The Innate Knowledge thesis asserts the existence of knowledge whose source is our own nature: we are born with this knowledge; it doesn’t depend, for its justification, on our accessing it via particular experiences. Our innate knowledge is not learned through either experience or intuition/deduction. It is just part of our nature. Experiences may trigger a process by which we bring this knowledge to consciousness, but these experiences do not provide us with the knowledge itself. It has in some way been with us all along. According to some rationalists, we gained the knowledge in an earlier existence. According to others, God provided us with it at creation. Still others say it is part of our nature through natural selection.

We get different versions of the Innate Knowledge thesis by substituting different subject areas for the variable ‘S’. The more subjects included within the range of the thesis or the more controversial the claim to have knowledge in them, the more radical the form of rationalism. Stronger and weaker understandings of warrant yield stronger and weaker versions of the thesis as well. Empiricists reject this thesis: Locke, for instance, dedicates the whole first book of the Essay to show that such knowledge, even if it existed, would be of little use to us.

The third important thesis that is relevant to the distinction between rationalism and empiricism is the Innate Concept thesis.

The Innate Concept Thesis : We have some of the concepts we employ in a particular subject area, S, as part of our rational nature.

According to the Innate Concept thesis, some of our concepts are not gained from experience. They are part of our rational nature in such a way that, while sense experiences may trigger a process by which they are brought to consciousness, experience does not provide the concepts or determine the information they contain. Some claim that the Innate Concept thesis is entailed by the Innate Knowledge Thesis; a particular instance of knowledge can only be innate if the concepts that are contained in the known proposition are also innate. This is Locke’s position ( Essay , 1.4.1). Others, such as Carruthers, argue against this connection (1992, pp. 53–54). The content and strength of the Innate Concept thesis varies with the concepts claimed to be innate. The more a concept seems removed from experience and the mental operations we can perform on experience the more plausibly it may be claimed to be innate. Since we do not experience perfect triangles but do experience pains, our concept of the former is a more promising candidate for being innate than our concept of the latter.

The Intuition/Deduction thesis, the Innate Knowledge thesis, and the Innate Concept thesis are essential to rationalism. Since the Intuition/Deduction thesis is equally important to empiricism, the focus in what follows will be on the other two theses. To be a rationalist is to adopt at least one of them: either the Innate Knowledge thesis, regarding our presumed propositional innate knowledge, or the Innate Concept thesis, regarding our supposed innate knowledge of concepts.

Rationalists vary the strength of their view by adjusting their understanding of warrant. Some take warranted beliefs to be beyond even the slightest doubt and claim that intuition provide beliefs of this high epistemic status. Others interpret warrant more conservatively, say as belief beyond a reasonable doubt, and claim that intuition provide beliefs of that caliber. Still another dimension of rationalism depends on how its proponents understand the connection between intuition, on the one hand, and truth, on the other. Some take intuition to be infallible, claiming that whatever we intuit must be true. Others allow for the possibility of false intuited propositions.

Two other closely related theses are generally adopted by rationalists, although one can certainly be a rationalist without adopting either of them. The first is that sense experience cannot provide what we gain from reason.

The Indispensability of Reason Thesis : The knowledge we gain in subject area, S, by intuition and deduction, as well as the ideas and instances of knowledge in S that are innate to us, could not have been gained by us through sense experience.

The second is that reason is superior to sense experience as a source of knowledge.

The Superiority of Reason Thesis : The knowledge we gain in subject area S by intuition and deduction or have innately is superior to any knowledge gained by sense experience.

How reason is superior needs explanation, and rationalists have offered different accounts. One view, generally associated with Descartes ( Rules, Rule II and Rule III, pp. 1–4), is that what we know by intuition is certain, beyond even the slightest doubt, while what we believe, or even know, on the basis of sense experience is at least somewhat uncertain. Another view, generally associated with Plato ( Republic 479e-484c), locates the superiority of a priori knowledge in the objects known. What we know by reason alone, a Platonic form, say, is superior in an important metaphysical way, e.g. unchanging, eternal, perfect, a higher degree of being, to what we are aware of through sense experience.

Most forms of rationalism involve notable commitments to other philosophical positions. One is a commitment to the denial of scepticism for at least some area of knowledge. If we claim to know some truths by intuition or deduction or to have some innate knowledge, we obviously reject scepticism with regard to those truths. Rationalism in the form of the Intuition/Deduction thesis is also committed to epistemic foundationalism, the view that we know some truths without basing our belief in them on any others and that we then use this foundational knowledge to know more truths.

Empiricists also endorse the Intuition/Deduction thesis, but in a more restricted sense than the rationalists: this thesis applies only to relations of the contents of our minds, not also about empirical facts, learned from the external world. By contrast, empiricists reject the Innate Knowledge and Innate Concept theses. Insofar as we have knowledge in a subject, our knowledge is gained , not only triggered, by our experiences, be they sensorial or reflective. Experience is, thus, our only source of ideas. Moreover, they reject the corresponding version of the Superiority of Reason thesis. Since reason alone does not give us any knowledge, it certainly does not give us superior knowledge. Empiricists need not reject the Indispensability of Reason thesis, but most of them do.

The main characteristic of empiricism, however, is that it endorses a version of the following claim for some subject area:

The Empiricism Thesis : We have no source of knowledge in S or for the concepts we use in S other than experience.

To be clear, the Empiricism thesis does not entail that we have empirical knowledge. It entails that knowledge can only be gained, if at all , by experience. Empiricists may assert, as some do for some subjects, that the rationalists are correct to claim that experience cannot give us knowledge. The conclusion they draw from this rationalist lesson is that we do not know at all. This is, indeed, Hume's position with regard to causation, which, he argues, is not actually known, but only presupposed to be holding true, in virtue of a particular habit of our minds.

We have stated the basic claims of rationalism and empiricism so that each is relative to a particular subject area. Rationalism and empiricism, so relativized, need not conflict. We can be rationalists in mathematics or a particular area of mathematics and empiricists in all or some of the physical sciences. Rationalism and empiricism only conflict when formulated to cover the same subject. Then the debate, Rationalism vs. Empiricism, is joined. The fact that philosophers can be both rationalists and empiricists has implications for the classification schemes often employed in the history of philosophy, especially the one traditionally used to describe the Early Modern Period of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries leading up to Kant. It is standard practice to group the philosophers of this period as either rationalists or empiricists and to suggest that those under one heading share a common agenda in opposition to those under the other. Thus, Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz are the Continental Rationalists in opposition to Locke, Hume, and Reid, the British Empiricists. Such general classification schemes should only be adopted with great caution. The views of the individual philosophers are a lot more subtle and complex than the simple-minded classification suggests. (See Loeb (1981) and Kenny (1986) for important discussions of this point.) Locke rejects rationalism in the form of any version of the Innate Knowledge or Innate Concept theses, but he nonetheless adopts the Intuition/Deduction thesis with regard to our knowledge of God’s existence, in addition to our knowledge of mathematics and morality. Descartes and Locke have remarkably similar views on the nature of our ideas, even though Descartes takes many to be innate, while Locke ties them all to experience. The rationalist/empiricist classification also encourages us to expect the philosophers on each side of the divide to have common research programs in areas beyond epistemology. Thus, Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz are mistakenly seen as applying a reason-centered epistemology to a common metaphysical agenda, with each trying to improve on the efforts of the one before, while Locke, Hume, and Reid are mistakenly seen as gradually rejecting those metaphysical claims, with each consciously trying to improve on the efforts of his predecessors. It is also important to note that the rationalist/empiricist distinction is not exhaustive of the possible sources of knowledge. One might claim, for example, that we can gain knowledge in a particular area by a form of Divine revelation or insight that is a product of neither reason nor sense experience. In short, when used carelessly, the labels ‘rationalist’ and ‘empiricist,’ as well as the slogan that is the title of this essay, ‘Rationalism vs. Empiricism,’ can impede rather than advance our understanding.

An important wrinkle for using this classification scheme in the history of philosophy is that it leaves out discussions of philosophical figures who did not focus their efforts on understanding whether innate knowledge is possible or even fruitful to have. Philosophy in the early modern period, in particular, is a lot richer than this artificial, simplifying distinction makes it sound. There is no clear way of grouping Hobbes with either camp, let alone Elizabeth of Bohemia, Anne Conway, George Berkeley, Émilie du Châtelet, or Mary Shepherd. This distinction, initially applied by Kant, is responsible for giving us a very restrictive philosophical canon, which does not take into account developments in the philosophy of emotions, philosophy of education, and even disputes in areas of philosophy considered more mainstream, like ethics and aesthetics.

Unless restricted to debates regarding the possibility of innate knowledge, this distinction is best left unused. The most interesting form of the debate occurs when we take the relevant subject to be truths about the external world, the world beyond our own minds. A full-fledged rationalist with regard to our knowledge of the external world holds that some external world truths are and must be innate and that this knowledge is superior to any that sense experience could ever provide. The full-fledged empiricist about our knowledge of the external world replies that, when it comes to the nature of the world beyond our own minds, experience is our sole source of information. Reason might inform us of the relations among our ideas, but those ideas themselves can only be gained, and any truths about the external reality they represent can only be known, on the basis of experience. This debate concerning our knowledge of the external world will generally be our main focus in what follows.

Historically, the rationalist/empiricist dispute in epistemology has extended into the area of metaphysics, where philosophers are concerned with the basic nature of reality, including the existence of God and such aspects of our nature as free-will and the relation between the mind and body. Several rationalists (e.g., Descartes, Meditations ) have presented metaphysical theories, which they have claimed to know by intuition and/or deduction alone. Empiricists (e.g., Hume, Treatise) have rejected the theories as either speculation, beyond what we can learn from experience, or nonsensical attempts to describe aspects of the world beyond the concepts experience can provide. The debate raises the issue of metaphysics as an area of knowledge. Kant puts the driving assumption clearly:

The very concept of metaphysics ensures that the sources of metaphysics can’t be empirical. If something could be known through the senses, that would automatically show that it doesn’t belong to metaphysics; that’s an upshot of the meaning of the word ‘metaphysics.’ Its basic principles can never be taken from experience, nor can its basic concepts; for it is not to be physical but metaphysical knowledge, so it must be beyond experience. ( Prolegomena , Preamble, I, p. 7)

The possibility then of metaphysics so understood, as an area of human knowledge, hinges on how we resolve the rationalist/empiricist debate. The debate also extends into ethics. Some moral objectivists (e.g., Ross 1930 and Huemer 2005) take us to know some fundamental objective moral truths by intuition, while some moral skeptics, who reject such knowledge (e.g., Mackie 1977), find the appeal to a faculty of moral intuition utterly implausible. More recently, the rationalist/empiricist debate has extended to discussions (e.g., Bealer 1999 and Alexander & Weinberg 2007) of the very nature of philosophical inquiry: to what extent are philosophical questions to be answered by appeals to reason or experience?

The Intuition/Deduction thesis claims that we can know some propositions by intuition and still more by deduction. Since traditionally this thesis was thought to be rejected by empiricists and adopted only by rationalists, it is useful to become more familiar with it. In a very narrow sense, only rationalists seem to adopt it. However, the current consensus is that most empiricists (e.g., Locke, Hume, Reid) have been willing to accept a version of the thesis, namely inasmuch as it is restricted to propositions solely about the relations among our own concepts. We can, they agree, know by intuition that our concept of God includes our concept of omniscience. Just by examining the concepts, we can intellectually grasp that the one includes the other. The debate between rationalists and empiricists is joined when the former assert, and the latter deny, the Intuition/Deduction thesis with regard to propositions that contain substantive information about the external world. Rationalists, such as Descartes, have claimed that we can know by intuition and deduction that God exists and created the world, that our mind and body are distinct substances, and that the angles of a triangle equal two right angles, where all of these claims are truths about an external reality independent of our thought. Such substantive versions of the Intuition/Deduction thesis are our concern in this section.

One defense of the Intuition/Deduction thesis assumes that we know some substantive external world truths, adds an analysis of what knowledge requires, and concludes that our knowledge must result from intuition and deduction. Rationalists and empiricists alike claim that certainty is required for scientia (which is a type of absolute knowledge of the necessary connections that would explain why certain things are a certain way) and that certainty about the external world is beyond what empirical evidence can provide. Empiricists seem happy to then conclude that the type of knowledge of the external world that we can acquire does not have this high degree of certainty and is, thus, not scientia . This is because we can never be sure our sensory impressions are not part of a dream or a massive, demon orchestrated, deception. A rationalist like Descartes of the Meditations , claims that only intuition can provide the certainty needed for such knowledge. This, after his arguing in the Rules that, when we “review all the actions of the intellect by means of which we are able to arrive at a knowledge of things with no fear of being mistaken,” we “recognize only two: intuition and deduction” ( Rules , Rule III, p. 3).

This line of argument is one of the least compelling in the rationalist arsenal. First, the assumption that knowledge requires certainty comes at a heavy cost, as it rules out so much of what we commonly take ourselves to know. Second, as many contemporary rationalists accept, intuition is not always a source of certain knowledge. The possibility of a deceiver gives us a reason to doubt our intuitions as well as our empirical beliefs. For all we know, a deceiver might cause us to intuit false propositions, just as one might cause us to have perceptions of nonexistent objects. Descartes’s classic way of meeting this challenge in the Meditations is to argue that we can know with certainty that no such deceiver interferes with our intuitions and deductions. They are infallible, as God guarantees their truth. The problem, known as the Cartesian Circle, is that Descartes’s account of how we gain this knowledge begs the question, by attempting to deduce the conclusion that all our intuitions are true from intuited premises. Moreover, his account does not touch a remaining problem that he himself notes ( Rules , Rule VII, p. 7): Deductions of any appreciable length rely on our fallible memory.

A more plausible argument for the Intuition/Deduction thesis again assumes that we know some particular, external world truths, and then appeals to the nature of what we know, rather than to the nature of knowledge itself, to argue that our knowledge must result from intuition and deduction. Leibniz, in New Essays , tells us the following:

The senses, although they are necessary for all our actual knowledge, are not sufficient to give us the whole of it, since the senses never give anything but instances, that is to say particular or individual truths. Now all the instances which confirm a general truth, however numerous they may be, are not sufficient to establish the universal necessity of this same truth, for it does not follow that what happened before will happen in the same way again. … From which it appears that necessary truths, such as we find in pure mathematics, and particularly in arithmetic and geometry, must have principles whose proof does not depend on instances, nor consequently on the testimony of the senses, although without the senses it would never have occurred to us to think of them… ( New Essays , Preface, pp. 150–151)

Leibniz goes on to describe our mathematical knowledge as “innate,” and his argument is more commonly directed to support the Innate Knowledge thesis rather than the Intuition/Deduction thesis. For our purposes here, we can relate it to the latter, however: We have substantive knowledge about the external world in mathematics, and what we know in that area, we know to be necessarily true. Experience cannot warrant beliefs about what is necessarily the case. Hence, experience cannot be the source of our knowledge. The best explanation of our knowledge is that we gain it by intuition and deduction. Leibniz mentions logic, metaphysics, and morals as other areas in which our knowledge similarly outstrips what experience can provide. Judgments in logic and metaphysics involve forms of necessity beyond what experience can support. Judgments in morals involve a form of obligation or value that lies beyond experience, which only informs us about what is the case rather than about what ought to be.

The strength of this argument varies with its examples of purported knowledge. Insofar as we focus on controversial claims in metaphysics, e.g., that God exists, that our mind is a distinct substance from our body, the initial premise that we know the claims is less than compelling. Taken with regard to other areas, however, the argument clearly has legs. We know a great deal of mathematics, and what we know, we know to be necessarily true. None of our experiences warrants a belief in such necessity, and we do not seem to base our knowledge on any experiences. The warrant that provides us with knowledge arises from an intellectual grasp of the propositions which is clearly part of our learning. Similarly, we seem to have such moral knowledge as that, all other things being equal, it is wrong to break a promise and that pleasure is intrinsically good. No empirical lesson about how things are can warrant such knowledge of how they ought to be.

This argument for the Intuition/Deduction thesis raises additional questions which rationalists must answer. Insofar as they maintain that our knowledge of necessary truths in mathematics or elsewhere by intuition and deduction is substantive knowledge of the external world, they owe us an account of this form of necessity. Many empiricists stand ready to argue that “necessity resides in the way we talk about things, not in the things we talk about” (Quine 1966, p. 174). Similarly, if rationalists claim that our knowledge in morals is knowledge of an objective form of obligation, they owe us an account of how objective values are part of a world of apparently valueless facts.

Perhaps most of all, any defenders of the Intuition/Deduction thesis owe us an account of what intuition is and how it provides warranted true beliefs about the external world. What is it to intuit a proposition and how does that act of intuition support a warranted belief? Their argument presents intuition and deduction as an explanation of assumed knowledge that can’t—they say—be explained by experience, but such an explanation by intuition and deduction requires that we have a clear understanding of intuition and how it supports warranted beliefs. Metaphorical characterizations of intuition as intellectual “grasping” or “seeing” are not enough, and if intuition is some form of intellectual “grasping,” it appears that all that is grasped is relations among our concepts, rather than facts about the external world, as the empiricists defenders of intuition and deduction argue. One current approach to the issue involves an appeal to Phenomenal Conservatism (Huemer 2001), the principle that if it seems to one as if something is the case, then one is prima facie justified in believing that it is so. Intuitions are then taken to be a particular sort of seeming or appearance: “[A]n intuition that p is a state of its seeming to one that p that is not dependent on inference from other beliefs and that results from thinking about p, as opposed to perceiving, remembering, or introspecting” (Huemer 2005, p. 102). Just as it can visually seem or appear to one as if there’s a tree outside the window, it can intellectually seem or appear to one as if nothing can be both entirely red and entirely green. This approach aims to demystify intuitions; they are but one more form of seeming-state along with ones we gain from sense perception, memory, and introspection. It does not, however, tell us all we need to know. Any intellectual faculty, whether it be sense perception, memory, introspection or intuition, provides us with warranted beliefs only if it is generally reliable. The reliability of sense perception stems from the causal connection between how external objects are and how we experience them. What accounts for the reliability of our intuitions regarding the external world? Is our intuition of a particular true proposition the outcome of some causal interaction between ourselves and some aspect of the world? What aspect? What is the nature of this causal interaction? That the number three is prime does not appear to cause anything, let alone our intuition that it is prime. As Michael Huemer (2005, p. 123) points out in mounting his own defense of moral intuitionism, “The challenge for the moral realist, then, is to explain how it would be anything more than chance if my moral beliefs were true, given that I do not interact with moral properties.”

These issues are made all the more pressing by the classic empiricist response to the argument. The reply is generally credited to Hume and begins with a division of all true propositions into two categories.

All the objects of human reason or inquiry may naturally be divided into two kinds, to wit, “Relations of Ideas,” and “Matters of Fact.” Of the first are the sciences of Geometry, Algebra, and Arithmetic, and, in short, every affirmation which is either intuitively or demonstratively certain. That the square of the hypotenuse is equal to the square of the two sides is a proposition which expresses a relation between these figures. That three times five is equal to half of thirty expresses a relation between these numbers. Propositions of this kind are discoverable by the mere operation of thought, without dependence on what is anywhere existent in the universe. Though there never were a circle or triangle in nature, the truths demonstrated by Euclid would forever retain their certainty and evidence. Matters of fact, which are the second objects of human reason, are not ascertained in the same manner, nor is our evidence of their truth, however great, of a like nature with the foregoing. The contrary of every matter of fact is still possible, because it can never imply a contradiction and is conceived by the mind with the same facility and distinctness as if ever so conformable to reality. ( Enquiry , 4.1, p. 24)

Intuition and deduction can provide us with knowledge of necessary truths such as those found in mathematics and logic, but such knowledge is not substantive knowledge of the external world. It is only knowledge of the relations of our own ideas. If the rationalist shifts the argument so it appeals to knowledge in morals, Hume’s reply is to offer an analysis of our moral concepts by which such knowledge is empirically gained knowledge of matters of fact.

Morals and criticism are not so properly objects of the understanding as of taste and sentiment. Beauty, whether moral or natural, is felt more properly than perceived. Or if we reason concerning it and endeavor to fix the standard, we regard a new fact, to wit, the general taste of mankind, or some other fact which may be the object of reasoning and inquiry. ( Enquiry , 12.3, p. 122)

If the rationalist appeals to our knowledge in metaphysics to support the argument, Hume denies that we have such knowledge.

If we take in our hand any volume--of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance--let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames, for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion. ( Enquiry , 12.3, p. 123)

An updated version of this general empiricist reply, with an increased emphasis on language and the nature of meaning, is given in the twentieth-century by A. J. Ayer’s version of logical positivism. Adopting positivism’s verification theory of meaning, Ayer assigns every cognitively meaningful sentence to one of two categories: either it is a tautology, and so true solely by virtue of the meaning of its terms and provides no substantive information about the world, or it is open to empirical verification. There is, then, no room for knowledge about the external world by intuition or deduction.

There can be no a priori knowledge of reality. For … the truths of pure reason, the propositions which we know to be valid independently of all experience, are so only in virtue of their lack of factual content … [By contrast] empirical propositions are one and all hypotheses which may be confirmed or discredited in actual sense experience. (Ayer 1952, pp. 86; 93–94)

The rationalists’ argument for the Intuition/Deduction thesis goes wrong at the start, according to empiricists, by assuming that we can have substantive knowledge of the external world that outstrips what experience can warrant. We cannot.

This empiricist reply faces challenges of its own. Our knowledge of mathematics seems to be about something more than our own concepts. Our knowledge of moral judgments seems to concern not just how we feel or act but how we ought to behave. The general principles that provide a basis for the empiricist view, e.g. Hume’s overall account of our ideas, the Verification Principle of Meaning, are problematic in their own right.

In all, rationalists have an argument for the Intuition/Deduction thesis relative to our substantive knowledge of the external world, but its success rests on how well they can answer questions about the nature and epistemic force of intuition made all the more pressing by the classic empiricist reply.

The Innate Knowledge thesis asserts that we have a priori knowledge, that is knowledge independent, for its justification, of sense experience, as part of our rational nature. Experience may trigger our awareness of this knowledge, but it does not provide us with it. The knowledge is already there.

Plato presents an early version of the Innate Knowledge thesis in the Meno as the doctrine of knowledge by recollection. The doctrine is motivated in part by a paradox that arises when we attempt to explain the nature of inquiry. How do we gain knowledge of a theorem in geometry? We inquire into the matter. Yet, knowledge by inquiry seems impossible ( Meno , 80d-e). We either already know the theorem at the start of our investigation or we do not. If we already have the knowledge, there is no place for inquiry. If we lack the knowledge, we don’t know what we are seeking and cannot recognize it when we find it. Either way we cannot gain knowledge of the theorem by inquiry. Yet, we do know some theorems.

The doctrine of knowledge by recollection offers a solution. When we inquire into the truth of a theorem, we both do and do not already know it. We have knowledge in the form of a memory gained from our soul’s knowledge of the theorem prior to its union with our body. We also lack some knowledge because, in our soul’s unification with the body, it has forgotten the knowledge and now needs to recollect it. Thus, learning the theorem allows us, in effect, to recall what we already know.

Plato famously illustrates the doctrine with an exchange between Socrates and a young slave, in which Socrates guides the slave from ignorance to mathematical knowledge. The slave’s experiences, in the form of Socrates’ questions and illustrations, are the occasion for his recollection of what he learned previously. Plato’s metaphysics provides additional support for the Innate Knowledge Thesis. Since our knowledge is of abstract, eternal Forms, which clearly lie beyond our sensory experience, it is independent, for its justification, of experience.

Contemporary supporters of Plato’s position are scarce. The initial paradox, which Plato describes as a “trick argument” ( Meno , 80e), rings sophistical. The metaphysical assumptions in the solution need justification. The solution does not answer the basic question: Just how did the slave’s soul learn the theorem? The Intuition/Deduction thesis offers an equally, if not more, plausible account of how the slave gains this type of knowledge that is independent of experience. Nonetheless, Plato’s position illustrates the kind of reasoning that has caused many philosophers to adopt some form of the Innate Knowledge thesis. We are confident that we know certain propositions about the external world, but there seems to be no adequate explanation of how we gained this knowledge short of saying that it is innate. Its content is beyond what we directly gain in experience, as well as what we can gain by performing mental operations on what experience provides. It does not seem to be based on an intuition or deduction. That it is innate in us appears to be the best explanation.

Noam Chomsky argues along similar lines in presenting what he describes as a “rationalist conception of the nature of language” (1975, p. 129). Chomsky argues that the experiences available to language learners are far too sparse to account for their knowledge of their language. To explain language acquisition, we must assume that learners have an innate knowledge of a universal grammar capturing the common deep structure of natural languages. It is important to note that Chomsky’s language learners do not know particular propositions describing a universal grammar. They have a set of innate capacities or dispositions which enable and determine their language development. Chomsky gives us a theory of innate learning capacities or structures rather than a theory of innate knowledge. His view does not support the Innate Knowledge thesis as rationalists have traditionally understood it. As one commentator puts it, “Chomsky’s principles … are innate neither in the sense that we are explicitly aware of them, nor in the sense that we have a disposition to recognize their truth as obvious under appropriate circumstances. And hence it is by no means clear that Chomsky is correct in seeing his theory as following the traditional rationalist account of the acquisition of knowledge” (Cottingham 1984, p. 124). Indeed, such a theory, which places nativism at the level of mental capacities or structures enabling us to acquire certain types of knowledge rather than at the level of knowledge we already posses, is akin to an empiricist take on the issue. Locke and Reid, for instance, believe that the human mind is endowed with certain abilities that, when developed in the usual course of nature, will lead us to acquire useful knowledge of the external world. The main idea is that it is part of our biology to have a digestive system that, when fed the right kind of food, allows us to process the required nutrients to enable us to continue to live for a while. Similarly, it is part of our biology to have a mental architecture that, when fed the right kind of information and experiences, allows us to process that information and transform it into knowledge. The knowledge itself is no more innate than the processed nutrients are. On a view like this, no knowledge is innate; however, we are born with certain capabilities and disposition that enable us to acquire knowledge, just as we are equipped with certain organs that allow our bodies to function well while we’re alive.

Peter Carruthers (1992) argues that we have innate knowledge of the principles of folk-psychology. Folk-psychology is a network of common-sense generalizations that hold independently of context or culture and concern the relationships of mental states to one another, to the environment and states of the body and to behavior (1992, p. 115). It includes such beliefs as that pains tend to be caused by injury, that pains tend to prevent us from concentrating on tasks, and that perceptions are generally caused by the appropriate state of the environment. Carruthers notes the complexity of folk-psychology, along with its success in explaining our behavior and the fact that its explanations appeal to such unobservables as beliefs, desires, feelings, and thoughts. He argues that the complexity, universality, and depth of folk-psychological principles outstrips what experience can provide, especially to young children who by their fifth year already know a great many of them. This knowledge is also not the result of intuition or deduction; folk-psychological generalizations are not seen to be true in an act of intellectual insight. Carruthers concludes, “[The problem] concerning the child’s acquisition of psychological generalizations cannot be solved, unless we suppose that much of folk-psychology is already innate, triggered locally by the child’s experience of itself and others, rather than learned” (1992, p. 121).

Empiricists, and some rationalists, attack the Innate Knowledge thesis in two main ways. First, they offer accounts of how sense experience or intuition and deduction provide the knowledge that is claimed to be innate. Second, they directly criticize the Innate Knowledge thesis itself. The classic statement of this second line of attack is presented in Locke’s Essay . Locke raises the issue of just what innate knowledge is. Particular instances of knowledge are supposed to be in our minds as part of our rational make-up, but how are they “in our minds”? If the implication is that we all consciously have this knowledge, it is plainly false. Propositions often given as examples of innate knowledge, even such plausible candidates as the principle that the same thing cannot both be and not be, are not consciously accepted by children and those with severe cognitive limitations. If the point of calling such principles “innate” is not to imply that they are or have been consciously accepted by all rational beings, then it is hard to see what the point is. “No proposition can be said to be in the mind, which it never yet knew, which it never yet was conscious of” ( Essay , 1.2.5). Proponents of innate knowledge might respond that some knowledge is innate in that we have the capacity to have it. That claim, while true, is of little interest, however. “If the capacity of knowing, be the natural impression contended for, all the truths a man ever comes to know, will, by this account, be every one of them, innate; and this great point will amount to no more, but only an improper way of speaking; which whilst it pretends to assert the contrary, says nothing different from those, who deny innate principles. For nobody, I think, ever denied, that the mind was capable of knowing several truths” ( Essay , 1.2.5). Locke thus challenges defenders of the Innate Knowledge thesis to present an account of innate knowledge that allows their position to be both true and interesting. A narrow interpretation of innateness faces counterexamples of rational individuals who do not meet its conditions. A generous interpretation implies that all our knowledge, even that clearly provided by experience, is innate.

Defenders of innate knowledge take up Locke’s challenge. Leibniz responds in New Essays by appealing to an account of innateness in terms of natural potential to avoid Locke’s dilemma. Consider Peter Carruthers’ similar reply.

We have noted that while one form of nativism claims (somewhat implausibly) that knowledge is innate in the sense of being present as such (or at least in propositional form) from birth, it might also be maintained that knowledge is innate in the sense of being innately determined to make its appearance at some stage in childhood. This latter thesis is surely the most plausible version of nativism. (1992, p. 51)

Carruthers claims that our innate knowledge is determined through evolutionary selection (p. 111). Evolution has resulted in our being determined to know certain things (e.g. principles of folk-psychology) at particular stages of our life, as part of our natural development. Experiences provide the occasion for our consciously believing the known propositions but not the basis for our knowledge of them (p. 52). Carruthers thus has a ready reply to Locke’s counterexamples of children and cognitively limited persons who do not believe propositions claimed to be instances of innate knowledge. The former have not yet reached the proper stage of development; the latter are persons in whom natural development has broken down (pp. 49–50).

A serious problem for the Innate Knowledge thesis remains, however. We know a proposition only if it is true, we believe it and our belief is warranted. Rationalists who assert the existence of innate knowledge are not just claiming that, as a matter of human evolution, God’s design or some other factor, at a particular point in our development, certain sorts of experiences trigger our belief in particular propositions in a way that does not involve our learning them from the experiences. Their claim is even bolder: In at least some of these cases, our empirically triggered, but not empirically warranted, belief is nonetheless warranted and so known. How can these beliefs be warranted if they do not gain their warrant from the experiences that cause us to have them or from intuition and deduction?

Some rationalists think that a reliabilist account of warrant provides the answer. According to Reliabilism, beliefs are warranted if they are formed by a process that generally produces true beliefs rather than false ones. The true beliefs that constitute our innate knowledge are warranted, then, because they are formed as the result of a reliable belief-forming process. Carruthers maintains that “Innate beliefs will count as known provided that the process through which they come to be innate is a reliable one (provided, that is, that the process tends to generate beliefs that are true)” (1992, p. 77). He argues that natural selection results in the formation of some beliefs and is a truth-reliable process.

An appeal to Reliabilism, or a similar causal theory of warrant, may well be the best way to develop the Innate Knowledge thesis. Even so, some difficulties remain. First, reliabilist accounts of warrant are themselves quite controversial. Second, rationalists must give an account of innate knowledge that maintains and explains the distinction between innate knowledge and non-innate knowledge, and it is not clear that they will be able to do so within such an account of warrant. Suppose for the sake of argument that we have innate knowledge of some proposition, P . What makes our knowledge that P innate? To sharpen the question, what difference between our knowledge that P and a clear case of non-innate knowledge, say our knowledge that something is red based on our current visual experience of a red table, makes the former innate and the latter not innate? In each case, we have a true, warranted belief. In each case, presumably, our belief gains its warrant from the fact that it meets a particular causal condition, e.g., it is produced by a reliable process. In each case, the causal process is one in which an experience causes us to believe the proposition at hand (that P ; that something is red), for, as defenders of innate knowledge admit, our belief that P is “triggered” by an experience, as is our belief that something is red. The insight behind the Innate Knowledge thesis seems to be that the difference between our innate and non-innate knowledge lies in the relation between our experience and our belief in each case. The experience that causes our belief that P does not “contain” the information that P , while our visual experience of a red table does “contain” the information that something is red. Yet, exactly what is the nature of this containment relation between our experiences, on the one hand, and what we believe, on the other, that is missing in the one case but present in the other? The nature of the experience-belief relation seems quite similar in each. The causal relation between the experience that triggers our belief that P and our belief that P is contingent, as is the fact that the belief-forming process is reliable. The same is true of our experience of a red table and our belief that something is red. The causal relation between the experience and our belief is again contingent. We might have been so constructed that the experience we describe as “being appeared to redly” caused us to believe, not that something is red, but that something is hot. The process that takes us from the experience to our belief is also only contingently reliable. Moreover, if our experience of a red table “contains” the information that something is red, then that fact, not the existence of a reliable belief-forming process between the two, should be the reason why the experience warrants our belief. By appealing to Reliabilism, or some other causal theory of warrant, rationalists may obtain a way to explain how innate knowledge can be warranted. They still need to show how their explanation supports an account of the difference between innate knowledge and non-innate knowledge. So, Locke's criticism -- that there is no true distinction between innate versus non-innate knowledge that rationalists may draw -- still stands, in the face of the best rationalist defense of the Innate Knowledge thesis.

According to the Innate Concept thesis, some of our concepts have not been gained from experience. They are instead part of our rational make-up, and experience simply triggers a process by which we consciously grasp them. The main concern motivating the rationalist should be familiar by now: the content of some concepts seems to outstrip anything we could have gained from experience. An example of this reasoning is presented by Descartes in the Meditations . Although he sometimes seems committed to the view that all our ideas are innate (Adams 1975 and Gotham 2002), he there classifies our ideas as adventitious, invented by us, and innate. Adventitious ideas, such as a sensation of heat, are gained directly through sense experience. Ideas invented by us, such as our idea of a hippogriff, are created by us from other ideas we possess. Innate ideas, such as our ideas of God, of extended matter, of substance, and of a perfect triangle, are placed in our minds by God at creation. Consider Descartes’s argument that our concept of God, as an infinitely perfect being, is innate. Our concept of God is not directly gained in experience, as particular tastes, sensations, and mental images might be. Its content is beyond what we could ever construct by applying available mental operations to what experience directly provides. From experience, we can gain the concept of a being with finite amounts of various perfections, one, for example, that is finitely knowledgeable, powerful and good. We cannot however move from these empirical concepts to the concept of a being of infinite perfection. (“I must not think that, just as my conceptions of rest and darkness are arrived at by negating movement and light, so my perception of the infinite is arrived at not by means of a true idea but by merely negating the finite,” Third Meditation, p. 94.) Descartes supplements this argument by another. Not only is the content of our concept of God beyond what experience can provide, the concept is a prerequisite for our employment of the concept of finite perfection gained from experience. (“My perception of the infinite, that is God, is in some way prior to my perception of the finite, that is myself. For how could I understand that I doubted or desired—that is lacked something—and that I was not wholly perfect, unless there were in me some idea of a more perfect being which enabled me to recognize my own defects by comparison,” Third Meditation, p. 94).

An empiricist response to this general line of argument is given by Locke ( Essay , 1.4.1–25). First, there is the problem of explaining what it is for someone to have an innate concept. If having an innate concept entails consciously entertaining it at present or in the past, then Descartes’s position is open to obvious counterexamples. Young children and people from other cultures do not consciously entertain the concept of God and have not done so. Second, there is the objection that we have no need to appeal to innate concepts in the first place. Contrary to Descartes’s argument, we can explain how experience provides all our ideas, including those the rationalists take to be innate, and with just the content that the rationalists attribute to them.

Leibniz’s New Essays offers a rationalist reply to the first concern. Where Locke puts forth the image of the mind as a blank slate on which experience writes, Leibniz offers us the image of a block of marble, the veins of which determine what sculpted figures it will accept ( New Essays , Preface, p. 153). Leibniz’s metaphor contains an insight that Locke misses. The mind plays a role in determining the nature of its contents. This point does not, however, require the adoption of the Innate Concept thesis. Locke might still point out that we are not required to have the concepts themselves and the ability to use them, innately. In contemporary terms, what we are required to have is the right hardware that allows for the optimal running of the actual software. For Locke, there are no constrains here; for Leibniz, only a particular type of software is, indeed, able to be supported by the extant hardware. Put differently, the hardware itself determines what software can be optimally run, for a Leibnizian.

Rationalists have responded to the second part of the empiricist attack on the Innate Concept thesis—the empiricists’ claim that the thesis is without basis, as all our ideas can be explained as derived from experience—by focusing on difficulties in the empiricists’ attempts to give such an explanation. The difficulties are illustrated by Locke’s account. According to Locke, experience consists in external sensation and inner reflection. All our ideas are either simple or complex, with the former being received by us passively in sensation or reflection and the latter being built by the mind from simple materials through various mental operations. Right at the start, the account of how simple ideas are gained is open to an obvious counterexample acknowledged, but then set aside, by Hume in presenting his own empiricist theory. Consider the mental image of a particular shade of blue. If Locke is right, the idea is a simple one and should be passively received by the mind through experience. Hume points out otherwise:

Suppose therefore a person to have enjoyed his sight for thirty years and to have become perfectly acquainted with colors of all kinds, except one particular shade of blue, for instance, which it never has been his fortune to meet with; let all the different shades of that color, except that single one, be placed before him, descending gradually from the deepest to the lightest, it is plain that he will perceive a blank where that shade is wanting and will be sensible that there is a greater distance in that place between the contiguous colors than in any other. Now I ask whether it be possible for him, from his own imagination, to supply this deficiency and raise up to himself the idea of that particular shade, though it had never been conveyed to him by his senses? I believe there are but few will be of the opinion that he can… ( Enquiry , 2, pp. 15–16)

Even when it comes to such simple ideas as the image of a particular shade of blue, the mind seems to be more than a blank slate on which experience writes. The main question is whether the veins in Leibniz’s metaphor should count as part of the knowledge or just as part of our biological mental architecture: all the knowledge we can ever acquire is constrained by the type of beings we are. This does not require our positing that concepts be part of the inner workings, at the beginning of our lives.

On the other hand, consider, too, our concept of a particular color, say red. Critics of Locke’s account have pointed out the weaknesses in his explanation of how we gain such a concept by the mental operation of abstraction on individual cases. For one thing, it makes the incorrect assumption that various instances of a particular concept share a common feature. Carruthers puts the objection as follows:

In fact problems arise for empiricists even in connection with the very simplest concepts, such as those of colour. For it is false that all instances of a given colour share some common feature. In which case we cannot acquire the concept of that colour by abstracting the common feature of our experience. Thus consider the concept red . Do all shades of red have something in common? If so, what? It is surely false that individual shades of red consist, as it were, of two distinguishable elements a general redness together with a particular shade. Rather, redness consists in a continuous range of shades, each of which is only just distinguishable from its neighbors. Acquiring the concept red is a matter of learning the extent of the range. (1992, p. 59)

For another thing, Locke’s account of concept acquisition from particular experiences seems circular: “For noticing or attending to a common feature of various things presupposes that you already possess the concept of the feature in question.” (Carruthers 1992, p. 55)

Consider in this regard Locke’s account of how we gain our concept of causation.

In the notice that our senses take of the constant vicissitude of things, we cannot but observe, that several particulars, both qualities and substances; begin to exist; and that they receive this their existence from the due application and operation of some other being. From this observation, we get our ideas of cause and effect. ( Essay , 2.26.1)

We get our concept of causation from our observation that some things receive their existence from the application and operation of some other things. Yet, to be able to make this observation, we must have our minds primed to do so. Rationalists argue that we cannot make this observation unless we already have the concept of causation. Empiricists, on the other hand, argue that our minds are constituted in a certain way, so that we can gain our ideas of causation and of power in a non-circular manner.

Rationalists would argue that Locke’s account of how we gain our idea of power displays a similar circularity.

The mind being every day informed, by the senses, of the alteration of those simple ideas, it observes in things without; and taking notice how one comes to an end, and ceases to be, and another begins to exist which was not before; reflecting also on what passes within itself, and observing a constant change of its ideas, sometimes by the impression of outward objects on the senses, and sometimes by the determination of its own choice; and concluding from what it has so constantly observed to have been, that the like changes will for the future be made in the same things, by like agents, and by the like ways, considers in one thing the possibility of having any of its simple ideas changed, and in another the possibility of making that change; and so comes by that idea which we call power. ( Essay , 2.21.1)

We come by the idea of power though considering the possibility of changes in our ideas made by experiences and our own choices. Yet, to consider this possibility—of some things making a change in others—we must already have a concept of power, rationalists would say. Empiricists, on the other hand, would point out, again, that what we actually need is for our minds to be able to recognize this, by having the correct abilities and faculties. Just as we don’t need to have a concept telling us how it is that we have binocular vision, being able to recognize change would be cashed out by us having the requisite faculty enabling us to do so.

Another way to meet at least some of these challenges to an empiricist account of the origin of our concepts is to revise our understanding of the content of our concepts so as to bring them more in line with what experience will clearly provide. Hume famously takes this approach. Beginning in a way reminiscent of Locke, he distinguishes between two forms of mental contents or “perceptions,” as he calls them: impressions and ideas. Impressions are the contents of our current experiences: our sensations, feelings, emotions, desires, and so on. Ideas are mental contents derived from impressions. Simple ideas are copies of impressions; complex ideas are derived from impressions by “compounding, transposing, augmenting or diminishing” them. Given that all our ideas are thus gained from experience, Hume offers us the following method for determining the content of any idea and thereby the meaning of any term taken to express it.

When we entertain, therefore, any suspicion that a philosophical term is employed without any meaning or idea (as is but too frequent), we need but inquire from what impression is that supposed idea derived ? And if it be impossible to assign any, this will confirm our suspicion. ( Enquiry , 2, p. 16)

Using this test, Hume draws out one of the most important implications of the empiricists’ denial of the Innate Concept thesis. If experience is indeed the source of all ideas, then our experiences also determine the content of our ideas. Our ideas of causation, of substance, of right and wrong have their content determined by the experiences that provide them. Those experiences, Hume argues, are unable to support the content that many rationalists and some empiricists, such as Locke, attribute to the corresponding ideas. Our inability to explain how some concepts, with the contents the rationalists attribute to them, are gained from experience should not lead us to adopt the Innate Concept thesis. It should lead us to accept a more limited view of the contents for those concepts, and thereby a more limited view of our ability to describe and understand the world.

Consider, for example, our idea of causation. Descartes takes it to be innate. Hume’s empiricist account severely limits its content. Our idea of causation is derived from a feeling of expectation rooted in our experiences of the constant conjunction of similar causes and effects.

It appears, then, that this idea of a necessary connection among events arises from a number of similar instances which occur, of the constant conjunction of these events; nor can that idea ever be suggested by any one of these instances surveyed in all possible lights and positions. But there is nothing in a number of instances, different from every single instance, which is supposed to be exactly similar, except only that after a repetition of similar instances the mind is carried by habit, upon the appearance of one event, to expect its usual attendant and to believe that it will exist. This connection, therefore, which we feel in the mind, this customary transition of the imagination from one object to its usual attendant, is the sentiment or impression from which we form the idea of power or necessary connection. ( Enquiry , 7.2, p. 59)

The source of our idea in experience determines its content.

Suitably to this experience, therefore, we may define a cause to be an object followed by another, and where all the objects, similar to the first are followed by objects similar to the second… We may, therefore, suitably to this experience, form another definition of cause and call it an object followed by another, and whose appearance always conveys the thought of the other . ( Enquiry , 7.2, p. 60)

Our claims, and any knowledge we may have, about causal connections in the world turn out, given the limited content of our empirically based concept of causation, to be claims and knowledge about the constant conjunction of events and our own feelings of expectation. Thus, the initial disagreement between rationalists and empiricists about the source of our ideas leads to one about their content and thereby the content of our descriptions and knowledge of the world.

Like philosophical debates generally, the rationalist/empiricist debate ultimately concerns our position in the world, in this case our position as rational inquirers. To what extent do our faculties of reason and experience support our attempts to know and understand our situation?

  • Adams, R., 1975, “Where Do Our Ideas Come From? Descartes vs Locke”, reprinted in Stitch S. (ed.) Innate Ideas , Berkeley, CA: California University Press.
  • Alexander, J. and Weinberg, J., 2007, “Analytic Epistemology and Experimental Philosophy,” Philosophy Compass , 2(1): 56–80.
  • Aune, B., 1970, Rationalism, Empiricism and Pragmatism: An Introduction , New York: Random House.
  • Ayer, A. J., 1952, Language, Truth and Logic , New York: Dover Publications.
  • Bealer, G., 1999, “A Theory of the A priori ,” Noûs , 33: 29–55.
  • Bealer, G. and Strawson, P. F., 1992, “The Incoherence of Empiricism,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 66: 99–143.
  • Boyle, D., 2009, Descartes on Innate Ideas , London: Continuum.
  • Bonjour, L., 1998, In Defense of Pure Reason , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Block, N., 1981, Essays in Philosophy of Psychology (Volume II), London: Methuen, Part Four.
  • Carruthers, P., 1992, Human Knowledge and Human Nature , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Casullo, A., 2003, A priori Knowledge and Justification , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Casullo, A. (ed.), 2012, Essays on A priori Knowledge and Justification , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Clarke, D., 1982, Descartes’ Philosophy of Science , Manchester: Manchester University Press.
  • Cottingham, J., 1984, Rationalism , London: Paladin Books.
  • Chomsky, N., 1975, “Recent Contributions to the Theory of Innate Ideas”, reprinted in S. Stitch (ed.), Innate Ideas , Berkeley, CA: California University Press.
  • –––, 1988, Language and Problems of Knowledge , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • De Paul, M. and W. Ramsey (eds.), 1998, Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and Its Role in Philosophical Inquiry , Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
  • De Rosa, R., 2004, “Locke’s Essay, Book I: The Question-Begging Status of the Anti-Nativist Arguments”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , 69: 37–64.
  • –––, 2000, “On Fodor’s Claim That Classical Empiricists and Rationalists Agree on the Innateness of Ideas”, ProtoSociology , 14: 240–269.
  • Descartes, R., 1628, Rules for the Direction of our Native Intelligence , in Descartes: Selected Philosophical Writings , John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988 [abbreviated as Rules ].
  • –––, 1641, Meditations , in Descartes: Selected Philosophical Writings , John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988 [abbreviated as Meditations ].
  • –––, 1644, Principles of Philosophy , in Descartes: Selected Philosophical Writings , John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988.
  • Falkenstein, L, 2004, “Nativism and the Nature of Thought in Reid’s Account of Our Knowledge of the External World”, in Terence Cuneo and Rene Van Woudenberg (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Reid , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 156–179.
  • Fodor, J., 1975, The Language of Thought , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1981, Representations , Brighton: Harvester.
  • Gorham, G., 2002, “Descartes on the Innateness of All Ideas,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy , 32(3): 355–388.
  • Huemer, M., 2001, Skepticism and the Veil of Perception , Lanham, Maryland: Rowman and Littlefield.
  • –––, 2005, Ethical Intuitionism , Hampshire: Palgrave MacMillan.
  • Hume, D., 1739–40, A Treatise of Human Nature , ed. David Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton, The Clarendon Edition of the Works of David Hume, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011 [abbreviated as Treatise ].
  • –––, 1748, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding , ed. Tom L. Beauchamp, The Clarendon Edition of the Works of David Hume, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000 [abbreviated as Enquiry ].
  • Kant, I., 1783, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysic , Jonathan Bennett (trans.), PDF available online at Early Modern Texts [abbreviated as Prolegomena ].
  • Kenny, A., 1986, Rationalism, Empiricism and Idealism , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Kripke, S., 1980, Naming and Necessity , Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Leibniz, G., c1704, New Essays on Human Understanding , in Leibniz: Philosophical Writings , G.H.R. Parkinson (ed.), Mary Morris and G.H.R. Parkinson (trans.), London: J.M. Dent & Sons, 1973 [abbreviated as New Essays ].
  • Locke, J., 1690, An Essay on Human Understanding , ed. Peter H. Nidditch, 1975 [abbreviated as Essay ].
  • Loeb, L., 1981, From Descartes to Hume: Continental Metaphysics and the Development of Modern Philosophy , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • Mackie, J. L., 1977, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong , London: Penguin Books.
  • Nadler, S., 2006, “The Doctrine of Ideas”, in S. Gaukroger (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Descartes’ Meditations , Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.
  • Plato, Meno , W. K. C. Guthrie (trans.), Plato: Collected Dialogues , edited by Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973.
  • Quine, W. V. O., 1966, Ways of Paradox and Other Essays , New York: Random House.
  • –––, 1951, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” in W.V.O. Quine, From a Logical Point of View , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1951.
  • Reid, T., 1785, Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man , ed. Derek Brookes and Knud Haakonssen, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2002 [abbreviated as Intellectual Powers ].
  • Ross, W. D., 1930, The Right and the Good , Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing, 1988.
  • Stitch, S., 1975, Innate Ideas , Berkeley, CA: California University Press.
  • Van Cleve, J., 2015, Problems from Reid , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Weinberg, S, 2016, Consciousness in Locke , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

analytic/synthetic distinction | a priori justification and knowledge | Ayer, Alfred Jules | Berkeley, George | concepts | Descartes, René | Descartes, René: theory of ideas | epistemology | Hume, David | innate/acquired distinction | innateness: and language | innateness: historical controversies | justification, epistemic: foundationalist theories of | Kant, Immanuel | knowledge: analysis of | Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm | Locke, John | Plato | Quine, Willard Van Orman | reliabilist epistemology | skepticism | Spinoza, Baruch

Copyright © 2021 by Peter Markie M. Folescu < folescum @ missouri . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

  • Skip to main content
  • Keyboard shortcuts for audio player

13.7 Cosmos & Culture

Can faith ever be rational.

Tania Lombrozo

A Carmelite nun in her cell in France in 1904.

Some people have faith that their spouse won't cheat on them. Some have faith that things happen for a reason. Some have faith in God.

Is there a common commitment underlying these disparate declarations of faith? And can such faith ever be rational?

I was prompted to think about these questions after reading the comments to my 13.7 post last week, " Science Vs. Religion: A Heated Debate Fueled By Disrespect ." There I argued that in debates about science, religion and (a)theism, all parties should seek "charitable ground":

"We should assume, as a default, that others hold their religious and scientific beliefs deeply, genuinely and reflectively."

Many readers responded that religious beliefs often aren't held "reflectively," and that scientific and religious beliefs are fundamentally different: The latter rest on faith as opposed to reason . The implication seemed to be that faith cannot be based on reason and, perhaps, that faith can never be rational. But is this right? Might faith be rational under some conditions? Could faith be warranted as an attitude one should (sometimes) adopt in guiding actions and beliefs?

To help me think about these weighty matters, I decided to read two recent papers ( one already published, with a more accessible version forthcoming) by Berkeley philosophy professor Lara Buchak. As an expert in decision theory and a philosopher of religion, she's in a unique position to tackle these very questions.

In evaluating the rationality of faith, we first need to be clear about what faith is , and that's where Buchak begins her analysis.

People commonly treat faith as something stronger than belief, as something one maintains despite evidence to the contrary. Buchak argues that there is a sense in which faith goes "beyond the evidence," but that it doesn't require believing something more strongly than the evidence suggests. Instead, Buchak characterizes faith as a commitment to acting as if some claim is true without first needing to examine additional evidence that could potentially bear on the claim .

To get the intuition behind this idea, it helps to consider some examples from Buchak's forthcoming paper :

If a man has faith that his spouse isn't cheating, this seems to rule out his hiring a private investigator, opening her mail, or even striking up a conversation with her boss to check that she really was working late last night—that is, it rules out conducting an inquiry to verify that his spouse isn't cheating. If he does any of these things, then she can rightfully complain that he didn't have faith in her, even if she realizes that, given his evidence, he should not assign degree of belief 1 to her constancy [i.e., even if he couldn't be 100% sure that she's been faithful]. To use a religious example, when so-called 'doubting' Thomas asks to put his hand in Jesus' side to verify that he has been resurrected in the flesh, this is supposed to indicate that he lacks faith.

In brief, faith requires a willingness to act as if something is true while also refraining from gathering evidence for the purpose of checking whether it's true.

But is it ever rational to agree to such terms? Isn't it always better to have more evidence rather than less; to make one's decisions after examining the largest and most reliable body of evidence possible?

Working from decision theory, rational choice theory, and her own novel mathematical results, Buchak draws a surprising conclusion: faith can sometimes be rational.

For faith to be rational, argues Buchak, a basic precondition first needs to be met: it must be the case that one thinks a claim sufficiently likely, and the actions it supports sufficiently beneficial, that the " expected utility " of acting on the claim outweighs the "expected utility" of not doing so. So, for example, if one assigns higher utility to a marriage in which both partners are faithful than to one in which either partner cheats, and one has good reason to believe that one's partner is in fact faithful, then the "expected utility" of being faithful oneself can outweigh that of cheating.

This precondition supports the rationality of acting in a way that's consistent with one's faith (e.g., of giving up an opportunity to cheat on one's spouse), but not necessarily of committing to doing so without recourse to further evidence (e.g., without investigating whether one's spouse is actually faithful). Buchak argues that this second condition for the rationality of faith will sometimes hold. The basic idea is that there are risks to making decisions about how to live your life – whether it's being faithful to your spouse or praying to God – in a way that's contingent on whether you've examined further evidence.

In the most straightforward cases, the costs associated with examining further evidence could outweigh the potential benefits. For example, the personal and financial costs that come with verifying the faithfulness of one's spouse could outweigh the differential benefits of cheating on a faithless spouse over remaining faithful to a true one. And if one's spouse is in fact faithful, then those costs will have been incurred for minimal benefits. One might feel slightly more secure in one's relationship, but the decision not to cheat won't have changed.

Another risk comes from the opportunities one loses in postponing a decision. If you hold off on trusting your spouse or in making a religious commitment, for example, you effectively give up the benefits of a particular kind of relationship (with your spouse, with God, with a religious community...) while you're hemming and hawing. You could also miss out on a great opportunity altogether (for true love, for a relationship with God...) if there's some possibility that the evidence you examine will be too inconclusive to support a decision or – worse yet – be misleading.

The details of Buchak's arguments get pretty technical pretty quickly, but the conclusions are easy to summarize. Roughly, faith will be more likely to be rational when one already has strong evidence for the claim in question (since further evidence will be less likely to drastically change one's mind), when the costs to examining further evidence are high (because those costs could outweigh differential benefits of acting differently), and when the evidence is likely to be inconclusive or misleading (because one could miss out on what was in fact a great opportunity).

While pretty abstract and theoretical, these conclusions turn out to support some intuitive guidelines for those hoping to be rational about their faith. In a conversation about her paper that we had by e-mail, Buchak offered the following succinct advice when it comes to trusting a partner or making a religious commitment:

Get evidence first! But don't postpone acting forever!

Of course, it doesn't follow from these arguments that religious faith – in general – is rational. Skeptics could argue that the condition of having strong evidence to begin with simply won't obtain when it comes to having faith in God, and New Atheists might argue that actions based on faith can themselves be costly to oneself and to others, challenging the idea that they'll ever yield greater expected utility.

Nonetheless, Buchak's paper suggests that under some conditions, faith can be rational, and sets the stage for a more sophisticated conversation about faith for theists and atheists alike. In our own conversation, Buchak shared the following reflections:

The way that religious faith is sometimes talked about in the larger cultural conversation can be harmful to everyone who is trying to find out the truth in religious matters and how they should live their lives. There's a naïve idea that faith requires believing against the evidence, or in the absence of evidence. When this idea is adopted by atheists, it can allow them to dismiss all religious faith as irrational by definition, without considering what the evidence is for particular religious claims. When this idea is adopted by religious people, it can allow them to think that believing against the evidence is a virtue, which is harmful to the pursuit of truth – it can also be psychologically harmful to try to believe something you think you don't have evidence for.

Sounds like an excellent basis for establishing more charitable ground!

You can keep up with more of what Tania Lombrozo is thinking on Twitter: @TaniaLombrozo

  • rationality
  • philosophy of religion
  • Lara Buchak
  • charitable ground
  • decision theory
  • WRITING CENTER
  • CUSTOMER AREA
  • Client Reviews
  • Our Writers
  • Sample Papers
  • Study Resources

Get Your Grades Improved by Our Professional Writers - We are Trusted by Thousands of Students!

Global compose inc. constantly employs professional homework writing help writers from usa, uk, ca and au. the writers are highly trained professionals, comprising of 500+ masters and ph.d level writers available 24/7. we assist clients who either have difficulty completing their assignments, sick or in need family time. to get started, submit your instructions., calculate your order price.

Use Discount Code: FIRST5 at Checkout FIRST5 -->

PRICE BEFORE DISCOUNT: $15.00

  • Philosophy Papers

Sample Essay on Is Rationalism Compatible With Religion?

Get homework help on this topic - check the quality of writing from this sample, if you are looking for assignment help on this topic or similar topic, click on order now button to submit your details. once we have your order details, your assignment will be assigned to one of our best writers, who will then proceed to write your paper and deliver it within your specified deadline. thank you for choosing us today.

Rationalism is a thought structure that underlines the function of reasoning in acquiring knowledge. Rationalism is not compatible with religion because, in the Islamic religion, an individual is not permitted to ask questions regarding the religion. Additionally, a lot of rationalistic perceptions emerge from individuals’ understanding of the Koran. In the Koran, Abdullah Ibn Abbas states that anyone who talks about the Koran based on his/her own view will burn in hell forever. The majority of Muslims have strong faith, which usually rebukes rationalistic opinions. Regarding faith, several rationalists in the religion are certain that it is not necessary to express faith physically. People who show their rational values do not physically believe. Therefore, rationalists can think about God and conclude that they are one with God. They question the reason for physically expressing their faith.

Concerning prayer, Muslims offer prayers to God five times each day. However, when rationalists pose questions about it, the religion responds that God gave that command and the prayer is regarded to be an endless and everyday discipline for Muslims. During prayer, Muslims engage in reciting the Koran, which contains God’s real words as well as instructions. They also show gratitude and bless God, and the prayer is regarded to be a plea to God. Prayer is among God’s laws , which Muslims should conform with. Nevertheless, the role of reason makes rationalism incompatible with religion.

According to the Islamic religion, nothing is considered more important than God. The term Islam denotes submission, whereas Muslim refers to a person who submits. Therefore, Islam stresses obedience to God. Some Muslim followers are categorized as doubters and deniers, and they believe that there is no need of practicing the faith since they are destined for heaven and hell. They refute the normal performances and can be categorized as rationalists. Such rationalists also ask questions about several topics and do not agree with the responses that are provided. Koran, 6: 21 states that a person who falsifies a lie against god and deceits about his communications is unjust and cannot succeed. The verse demonstrates proof to dispute the motivation of a rationalistic opinion of questioning God’s words. A rationalist can be termed as a “physical believer’ who queries anything that cannot be physically observed or heard.

The presence of God is a question with no certain answer. According to religion, God’s existence is the basis of all religions . However, rationalists think that because God’s existence is subject to doubt, he is not perfect and thus not the cause of existence. Muslims obtain God’s existence from His words in the Koran. Furthermore, religion has no error, and no questions should be raised concerning the existence of God as well as His words.

The origin of incompatibility between rationalism and religion is the aspect of the ‘physical believer.’ Individuals who question the unexplainable are not able to improve the intervening of rationalist thinking as well as religious teachings. Rationalism uses the power of reasoning to obtain understanding whereas religion entails believing and having faith.

Do you have an Assignment on a Similar or Related Topic? We can Help You Right Now! Click on the Order Now button...

Are you looking for homework writing help on this topic? This question was posted by one of our client seeking homework help.  If you are therefore looking for an assignment to submit, then click on  ORDER NOW button or contact us today. Our Professional Writers will be glad to write your paper from scratch, and delivered within your deadline. Perfect choice for your excellent grades! www.globalcompose.com.

We ensure that assignment instructions are followed, the paper is written from scratch. If you are not satisfied by our service, you can either request for refund or unlimited revisions for your order at absolutely no extra pay. Once the writer has completed your paper, the editors check your paper for any grammar/formatting/plagiarism mistakes, then the final paper is sent to your email.

Writing Features

Affordable Writing Services

Experienced Writing Team

24/7 Team of Writers

Professional E ssay Writers

Quality Measures

Trained Support Team

Non-Plagiarized Papers

Well Researched Papers

Free Writing Resources

Privacy | Confidentiality

We do not share your personal information with any company or person. we have also ensured that the ordering process is secure; you can check the security feature in the browser. for confidentiality purposes, all papers are sent to your personal email. if you have any questions, contact us any time via email, live chat or our phone number., our clients testimonials, a team of +500 masters and ph.d level homework writing help writers available 24/7 cannot get it wrong. the following are customer reviews about the quality of our services..

“Thanks for offering your professional assistance on this one. Topic was confusing but writer worked it out”

Added 24 Minutes Ago

“Thanks, I like the literature review, it is discussed in depth. Have looked at the results section and it is conclusive as I expected. Thank you”

Added 12 Hours Ago

“I like the discussion on the case study. Thank you. Am satisfied and wanted to request that same writer will handle my future assignments”

Added 30 Minutes Ago

“I was paranoid about online writing services, but on this one, the results are evident that you are much better. Will order more papers”

Added 3 Minutes Ago

“I think the paper is alright. If I can book the writer for the soon upcoming assignment, it will be great. Thanks”

Added 6 Minutes Ago

Why choose our homework writing help, we try to work as diligent as we can to help you meet your homework’s deadline. our support staff is always online 24/7 to help clarify any issues or concerns you have regarding our services. talk to us today to find out how our writers may be of help to you., customized papers, we consider your instructions and specifications in order to tailor the paper to suit your expectations., only professional writers, all our writers have a masters or ph.d and are well trained to handle assignments in various disciplines at different education levels., fast and reliable, our writers are capable of handling any assignment with short deadline and deliver without any delay, thus saving you time and energy, round the clock support, our customer support is always ready to offer real time assistance of day and night, through email, live-chat and phone., cost effective prices, we save you money with our affordable prices and huge discounts on all assignments., 100% original papers, all our papers are thoroughly researched and written from scratch. be sure of completely non-plagiarized papers., our ordering process, to get started with our homework writing help, simply click on the order now button. its easy, secure and takes less than 2 minutes to complete. the following steps illustrates the entire process., fill the order form: include all instructions and files for your assignment., submit your payment via card or paypal so that your order can be processed., a writer works on your paper and submits to editors upon completion., the completed paper is examined by our editors, then sent to your email, want to learn from experts check the writing tips below.

Final Paper Assignments

  • Thesis Writing Help
  • Dissertation Chapters
  • Writing Research Papers
  • Project Writing
  • Term Paper Writing
  • Speech Writing

Weekly Assignments

  • Essay Writing
  • Coursework Writing
  • Assignment Writing Help
  • Homework Writing Help
  • Book Review Writing
  • Movie Review Writing

Creative Assignments

  • Power Points Preparation
  • Analyzing Case Studies
  • Creative Writing Papers
  • Critical Thinking Writing
  • Annotated Bibliography
  • Capstone Project Writing

Admission Papers

  • Writing Scholarship Essay
  • Writing Admission Essays
  • Writing Application Essays
  • Writing Entrance Essays
  • Personal Statement Essays
  • Reaction Paper Writing

Samples of our Writing Illustrated Below

We have compiled a list of samples written by our writers for your review. you can use these samples to write your paper. you must however cite the source properly. if you are looking for a non-plagiarised paper, click on the order button. our professionals will work on your order. are you looking for writing tips check the list on this page. we are glad that we could help..

  • Discussion Essay Homework
  • Dissertation/Thesis Writing
  • Book Review Paper
  • Business Plan Homework
  • Capstone Project Paper
  • Creative Writing Homework
  • Critical Thinking Homework
  • Application Essay Homework
  • Case Study Homework
  • Literature Review Homework
  • Personal Reflection Homework
  • Reflection Essay Homework
  • Research Proposal Homework
  • Annotated bibliography Paper
  • Article Review Homework
  • Research Paper Homework
  • Movie Review Sample
  • Term Paper Sample
  • Admission Essay Homework
  • Argumentative Essay Paper
  • Response Essay Homework

A List of Related Papers On This Category is Provided Below

  • Sample Coursework Paper on Kant Reading Questions Fall 2015
  • Sample Essay on Antigone
  • Sample Essay on Illusion of Religion
  • Sample Article Review Paper on Philosophy
  • Sample Essay on Kant’s Philosophy
  • Sample Essay on Formative Evaluation
  • Sample Article Review Paper on Library Research Assignment #2- Retribution
  • Sample Paper on Human Prospect
  • Sample Research Paper on Utilitarianism
  • Sample Essay on Free Will and Determinism
  • Sample Critical Thinking Paper on Philosophy
  • Sample Presentation Paper on Disparities in Child Mortality: Saudi Arabia
  • Philosophy Sample Paper on What Theory Best Explains Moral Responsibility
  • Sample Term Paper on Revenge
  • Sample Essay on Philosophy
  • Sample Essay on the Mind-Body Problem
  • Sample Philosophy Paper on Forms of child labor
  • Sample Research Paper on what is Philosophy?
  • Sample Paper on Sweatshop Labor
  • Sample Essay on Conflict of Interest in Engineering

Get your Homework Written by our Top-Notch Writers Now

COMMENTS

  1. Rationalism

    rationalism, in Western philosophy, the view that regards reason as the chief source and test of knowledge.Holding that reality itself has an inherently logical structure, the rationalist asserts that a class of truths exists that the intellect can grasp directly. There are, according to the rationalists, certain rational principles—especially in logic and mathematics, and even in ethics and ...

  2. Rationalism

    Rationalism - Enlightenment, Reason, Beliefs: Stirrings of religious rationalism were already felt in the Middle Ages regarding the Christian revelation. Thus, the skeptical mind of Peter Abelard (1079-1142) raised doubts by showing in his Sic et non ("Yes and No") many contradictions among beliefs handed down as revealed truths by the Church Fathers.

  3. (PDF) "The Idea of a Rationalistic Philosophy of Religion and Its

    C H APTE R 1 8 The Idea of a Rationalistic Philosophy of Religion and Its Challenges One of the most important intellectual changes that has occurred within the Catholic Church in the last decades is the shift away from fideism toward rationalism—or, to be more precise, and to use comparative rather than classificatory concepts, a move from a ...

  4. Rationalism

    In philosophy, rationalism is the epistemological view that "regards reason as the chief source and test of knowledge" [1] or "any view appealing to reason as a source of knowledge or justification", [2] often in contrast to other possible sources of knowledge such as faith, tradition, or sensory experience.More formally, rationalism is defined as a methodology or a theory "in which the ...

  5. Faith and rationality

    Thomas Aquinas was the first to write a full treatment of the relationship, differences, and similarities between faith, which he calls "an intellectual assent", [5] and reason. [6]Dei Filius was a dogmatic constitution of the First Vatican Council on the Roman Catholic faith. It was adopted unanimously on 24 April 1870. It states that "not only can faith and reason never be opposed to one ...

  6. Rational Religion

    In New England, Jonathan Edwards was a significant figure who attempted to strike a balance between reason and traditional religion. Edwards was the pastor of the church in Northampton, Massachusetts, and was a leader of the Great Awakening, the evangelical revival that swept through many of the colonies beginning in the 1730s and 1740s.

  7. BBC

    Rationalism. Rationalism is an approach to life based on reason and evidence. Rationalism encourages ethical and philosophical ideas that can be tested by experience and rejects authority that ...

  8. Beyond Faith and Rationality: Essays on Logic, Religion and Philosophy

    Ricardo Sousa Silvestre holds a Ph.D. in Philosophy from the University of Montreal.He has been Visiting Scholar at the Universities of Oxford (UK), Notre Dame (USA) and Québec (Canada). He is the author of several papers on Logic and Philosophy of Religion and guest-editor of a couple of special issues on the field of Logic and Religion, namely the special issues on the Concept of God (2019 ...

  9. Religion and Rationality: Essays on Reason, God and Modernity

    Books. Religion and Rationality: Essays on Reason, God and Modernity. Jürgen Habermas. Wiley, Oct 15, 2014 - Philosophy - 184 pages. This important new volume brings together Habermas' key writing on religion and religious belief. Habermas explores the relations between Christian and Jewish thought, on the one hand, and the Western ...

  10. Philosophy of Religion

    Philosophy of religion is the philosophical examination of the themes and concepts involved in religious traditions as well as the broader philosophical task of reflecting on matters of religious significance including the nature of religion itself, alternative concepts of God or ultimate reality, and the religious significance of general features of the cosmos (e.g., the laws of nature, the ...

  11. Rationalism

    RATIONALISM. The term rationalism (from the Latin ratio, "reason") has been used to refer to several different outlooks and movements of ideas.By far the most important of these is the philosophical outlook or program that stresses the power of a priori reason to grasp substantial truths about the world and correspondingly tends to regard natural science as a basically a priori enterprise.

  12. The rationality of faith and the benefits of religion

    Religions don't simply make claims about the world; they also offer existential resources, resources for dealing with basic human problems, such as the need for meaning, love, identity, and personal growth. For instance, a Buddhist's resources for addressing these existential needs are different than a Christian's. Now, imagine someone who is agnostic but who is deciding whether to put ...

  13. Religion and Rationality: Essays on Reason, God and Modernity

    This important new volume brings together Habermas key writing on religion and religious belief. Habermas explores the relations between Christian and Jewish thought, on the one hand, and the Western philosophical tradition on the other. In so doing, he examines a range of important figures, including Benjamin, Heidegger, Johann Baptist Metz and Gershom Scholem. In a new introduction written ...

  14. Rationalism vs. Empiricism

    1. Introduction. The dispute between rationalism and empiricism takes place primarily within epistemology, the branch of philosophy devoted to studying the nature, sources, and limits of knowledge. Knowledge itself can be of many different things and is usually divided among three main categories: knowledge of the external world, knowledge of ...

  15. Rationalism

    The philosophy of rationalism states that knowledge is a priori, or previously known and gathered, in all human beings. It is not acquired over time, through various experiences, but intrinsic to ...

  16. Jewish Philosophy in the Middle Ages: Science, Rationalism, and Religion

    To write a book that's accessible to a wide audience, assuming no prior knowledge of Judaism or medieval thought, that contributes new insights to the academic community, and constitutes an intellectual history of Jewish thought from Isaac Israeli (832-932) all the way to Baruch Spinoza (1632-1677), including an important backward glance to Philo (b. 25 BCE), and to do so in a book of just ten ...

  17. Can Faith Ever Be Rational? : 13.7: Cosmos And Culture : NPR

    Working from decision theory, rational choice theory, and her own novel mathematical results, Buchak draws a surprising conclusion: faith can sometimes be rational. For faith to be rational ...

  18. God as Reason: Essays in Philosophical Theology

    God as Reason is a collection of essays, published between 1990-2011, in which Vittorio Hösle attempts "to find an interpretation of Christianity that is compatible with [his] commitment to reason" (p. viii). The term 'reason' is used here in a sense strongly influenced by German idealism, and also by Plato and Vico. Hösle presents himself as "today a Catholic", although "in his formative ...

  19. Role of Religion in Society: Exploring its Significance and

    This essay will examine the role of religion in society, considering its historical context, impact on culture and identity, role in social cohesion, implications for politics and morality, and the ongoing debate surrounding its place in modern society. A nuanced analysis highlights religion's complex and multidimensional influence.

  20. Sample Essay on Is Rationalism Compatible With Religion?

    Rationalism is a thought structure that underlines the function of reasoning in acquiring knowledge. Rationalism is not compatible with religion because, in the Islamic religion, an individual is not permitted to ask questions regarding the religion. Additionally, a lot of rationalistic perceptions emerge from individuals' understanding of ...