• Our Writers
  • How to Order
  • Assignment Writing Service
  • Report Writing Service
  • Buy Coursework
  • Dissertation Writing Service
  • Research Paper Writing Service
  • All Essay Services
  • Buy Research Paper
  • Buy Term Paper
  • Buy Dissertation
  • Buy Case study
  • Buy Presentation
  • Buy Personal statement

User Icon

Science Essay

Betty P.

Learn How to Write an A+ Science Essay

11 min read

science essay

People also read

150+ Engaging Science Essay Topics To Hook Your Readers

Read 13 Impressive Science Essay Examples And Get Inspired

Science Fiction Essay: Examples & Easy Steps Guide

Essay About Science and Technology| Tips & Examples

Essay About Science in Everyday Life - Samples & Writing Tips

Check Out 5 Impressive Essay About Science Fair Examples

Did you ever imagine that essay writing was just for students in the Humanities? Well, think again! 

For science students, tackling a science essay might seem challenging, as it not only demands a deep understanding of the subject but also strong writing skills. 

However, fret not because we've got your back!

With the right steps and tips, you can write an engaging and informative science essay easily!

This blog will take you through all the important steps of writing a science essay, from choosing a topic to presenting the final work.

So, let's get into it!

Arrow Down

  • 1. What Is a Science Essay?
  • 2. How To Write a Science Essay?
  • 3. How to Structure a Science Essay?
  • 4. Science Essay Examples
  • 5. How to Choose the Right Science Essay Topic
  • 6. Science Essay Topics
  • 7. Science Essay Writing Tips

What Is a Science Essay?

A science essay is an academic paper focusing on a scientific topic from physics, chemistry, biology, or any other scientific field.

Science essays are mostly expository. That is, they require you to explain your chosen topic in detail. However, they can also be descriptive and exploratory.

A descriptive science essay aims to describe a certain scientific phenomenon according to established knowledge.

On the other hand, the exploratory science essay requires you to go beyond the current theories and explore new interpretations.

So before you set out to write your essay, always check out the instructions given by your instructor. Whether a science essay is expository or exploratory must be clear from the start. Or, if you face any difficulty, you can take help from a science essay writer as well. 

Moreover, check out this video to understand scientific writing in detail.

Now that you know what it is, let's look at the steps you need to take to write a science essay. 

Order Essay

Paper Due? Why Suffer? That's our Job!

How To Write a Science Essay?

Writing a science essay is not as complex as it may seem. All you need to do is follow the right steps to create an impressive piece of work that meets the assigned criteria.

Here's what you need to do:

Choose Your Topic

A good topic forms the foundation for an engaging and well-written essay. Therefore, you should ensure that you pick something interesting or relevant to your field of study. 

To choose a good topic, you can brainstorm ideas relating to the subject matter. You may also find inspiration from other science essays or articles about the same topic.

Conduct Research

Once you have chosen your topic, start researching it thoroughly to develop a strong argument or discussion in your essay. 

Make sure you use reliable sources and cite them properly . You should also make notes while conducting your research so that you can reference them easily when writing the essay. Or, you can get expert assistance from an essay writing service to manage your citations. 

Create an Outline

A good essay outline helps to organize the ideas in your paper. It serves as a guide throughout the writing process and ensures you don’t miss out on important points.

An outline makes it easier to write a well-structured paper that flows logically. It should be detailed enough to guide you through the entire writing process.

However, your outline should be flexible, and it's sometimes better to change it along the way to improve your structure.

Start Writing

Once you have a good outline, start writing the essay by following your plan.

The first step in writing any essay is to draft it. This means putting your thoughts down on paper in a rough form without worrying about grammar or spelling mistakes.

So begin your essay by introducing the topic, then carefully explain it using evidence and examples to support your argument.

Don't worry if your first draft isn't perfect - it's just the starting point!

Proofread & Edit

After finishing your first draft, take time to proofread and edit it for grammar and spelling mistakes.

Proofreading is the process of checking for grammatical mistakes. It should be done after you have finished writing your essay.

Editing, on the other hand, involves reviewing the structure and organization of your essay and its content. It should be done before you submit your final work.

Both proofreading and editing are essential for producing a high-quality essay. Make sure to give yourself enough time to do them properly!

After revising the essay, you should format it according to the guidelines given by your instructor. This could involve using a specific font size, page margins, or citation style.

Most science essays are written in Times New Roman font with 12-point size and double spacing. The margins should be 1 inch on all sides, and the text should be justified.

In addition, you must cite your sources properly using a recognized citation style such as APA , Chicago , or Harvard . Make sure to follow the guidelines closely so that your essay looks professional.

Following these steps will help you create an informative and well-structured science essay that meets the given criteria.

Tough Essay Due? Hire Tough Writers!

How to Structure a Science Essay?

A basic science essay structure includes an introduction, body, and conclusion. 

Let's look at each of these briefly.

  • Introduction

Your essay introduction should introduce your topic and provide a brief overview of what you will discuss in the essay. It should also state your thesis or main argument.

For instance, a thesis statement for a science essay could be, 

"The human body is capable of incredible feats, as evidenced by the many athletes who have competed in the Olympic games."

The body of your essay will contain the bulk of your argument or discussion. It should be divided into paragraphs, each discussing a different point.

For instance, imagine you were writing about sports and the human body. 

Your first paragraph can discuss the physical capabilities of the human body. 

The second paragraph may be about the physical benefits of competing in sports. 

Similarly, in the third paragraph, you can present one or two case studies of specific athletes to support your point. 

Once you have explained all your points in the body, it’s time to conclude the essay.

Your essay conclusion should summarize the main points of your essay and leave the reader with a sense of closure.

In the conclusion, you reiterate your thesis and sum up your arguments. You can also suggest implications or potential applications of the ideas discussed in the essay. 

By following this structure, you will create a well-organized essay.

Check out a few example essays to see this structure in practice.

Science Essay Examples

A great way to get inspired when writing a science essay is to look at other examples of successful essays written by others. 

Here are some examples that will give you an idea of how to write your essay.

Science Essay About Genetics - Science Essay Example

Environmental Science Essay Example | PDF Sample

The Science of Nanotechnology

Science, Non-Science, and Pseudo-Science

The Science Of Science Education

Science in our Daily Lives

Short Science Essay Example

Let’s take a look at a short science essay: 

As we step into the 21st century, it is evident that the chalkboard and textbook are no longer the sole tools of education.

Technology has fundamentally reshaped education by offering improved learning experiences, enhancing accessibility, and equipping students with essential digital skills.

Technology enhances learning experiences by providing interactive and engaging educational content. Digital platforms offer multimedia resources, simulations, and virtual laboratories, enabling students to grasp complex concepts more effectively. For example, in the field of science, students can virtually dissect organisms, observe chemical reactions, and explore outer space—all from the comfort of their devices. These immersive experiences not only make learning more enjoyable but also deepen understanding and retention of the subject matter.

Lastly, technology equips students with essential digital skills vital for success in the modern workforce. Proficiency in using digital tools, software, and online research is becoming increasingly necessary in almost every career path. By incorporating technology into education, students not only acquire subject-specific knowledge but also develop crucial digital literacy and problem-solving skills that are highly sought after by employers.

In conclusion, technology's impact on modern education cannot be overstated. It enhances learning experiences, broadens access to education, and equips students with the digital skills they need to thrive in today's interconnected world. While traditional teaching methods still hold value, integrating technology into education is essential to prepare students for the challenges and opportunities of the digital age. As we move forward, it is crucial to strike a balance between technology and traditional pedagogy to provide a well-rounded education that prepares students for a diverse and dynamic future.

Want to read more essay examples? Here, you can find more science essay examples to learn from.

How to Choose the Right Science Essay Topic

Choosing the right science essay topic is a critical first step in crafting a compelling and engaging essay. Here's a concise guide on how to make this decision wisely:

  • Consider Your Interests: Start by reflecting on your personal interests within the realm of science. Selecting a topic that genuinely fascinates you will make the research and writing process more enjoyable and motivated.
  • Relevance to the Course: Ensure that your chosen topic aligns with your course or assignment requirements. Read the assignment guidelines carefully to understand the scope and focus expected by your instructor.
  • Current Trends and Issues: Stay updated with the latest scientific developments and trends. Opting for a topic that addresses contemporary issues not only makes your essay relevant but also demonstrates your awareness of current events in the field.
  • Narrow Down the Scope: Science is vast, so narrow your topic to a manageable scope. Instead of a broad subject like "Climate Change," consider a more specific angle like "The Impact of Melting Arctic Ice on Global Sea Levels."
  • Available Resources: Ensure that there are sufficient credible sources and research materials available for your chosen topic. A lack of resources can hinder your research efforts.
  • Discuss with Your Instructor: If you're uncertain about your topic choice, don't hesitate to consult your instructor or professor. They can provide valuable guidance and may even suggest specific topics based on your academic goals.

Science Essay Topics

Choosing an appropriate topic for a science essay is one of the first steps in writing a successful paper.

Here are a few science essay topics to get you started:

  • How space exploration affects our daily lives?
  • How has technology changed our understanding of medicine?
  • Are there ethical considerations to consider when conducting scientific research?
  • How does climate change affect the biodiversity of different parts of the world?
  • How can artificial intelligence be used in medicine?
  • What impact have vaccines had on global health?
  • What is the future of renewable energy?
  • How do we ensure that genetically modified organisms are safe for humans and the environment?
  • The influence of social media on human behavior: A social science perspective
  • What are the potential risks and benefits of stem cell therapy?

Important science topics can cover anything from space exploration to chemistry and biology. So you can choose any topic according to your interests!

Need more topics? We have gathered 100+ science essay topics to help you find a great topic!

Continue reading to find some tips to help you write a successful science essay. 

Science Essay Writing Tips

Once you have chosen a topic and looked at examples, it's time to start writing the science essay.

Here are some key tips for a successful essay:

  • Research thoroughly

Make sure you do extensive research before you begin writing your paper. This will ensure that the facts and figures you include are accurate and supported by reliable sources.

  • Use clear language

Avoid using jargon or overly technical language when writing your essay. Plain language is easier to understand and more engaging for readers.

  • Referencing

Always provide references for any information you include in your essay. This will demonstrate that you acknowledge other people's work and show that the evidence you use is credible.

Make sure to follow the basic structure of an essay and organize your thoughts into clear sections. This will improve the flow and make your essay easier to read.

  • Ask someone to proofread

It’s also a good idea to get someone else to proofread your work as they may spot mistakes that you have missed.

These few tips will help ensure that your science essay is well-written and informative!

You've learned the steps to writing a successful science essay and looked at some examples and topics to get you started. 

Make sure you thoroughly research, use clear language, structure your thoughts, and proofread your essay. With these tips, you’re sure to write a great science essay! 

Do you still need expert help writing a science essay? Our science essay writing service is here to help. With our team of professional writers, you can rest assured that your essay will be written to the highest standards.

Contact our essay service now to get started!

Also, do not forget to try our essay typer tool for quick and cost-free aid with your essays!

AI Essay Bot

Write Essay Within 60 Seconds!

Betty P.

Betty is a freelance writer and researcher. She has a Masters in literature and enjoys providing writing services to her clients. Betty is an avid reader and loves learning new things. She has provided writing services to clients from all academic levels and related academic fields.

Get Help

Paper Due? Why Suffer? That’s our Job!

Keep reading

science essay topics

How to Write a Scientific Essay

Scientific essays require you to produce a piece of work which has all the necessary details and facts around the topic. This may sound just like any other essay (for example, discussion, critical or compare and contrast), but there are some key differences which set a scientific essay apart.

The most important is that a science essay must be analytical and precise in the delivery of answers. This is because in science essays, there is no room for your opinion or a vague perspective – the aim is to identify objective or impartial logic and accurate knowledge, as well as giving you a forum to demonstrate your judgement and analysis skills. Our guideline to structure can ensure you deliver a premium level scientific paper.

Structure of a Scientific Paper

Introduction.

All essays need to encourage readers to want to read more. This is the main goal of the introduction. Defining the problem or research area clearly, so that readers understand what the work is about should be combined with a background context, and how your work fits into the current theoretical perspectives of the subject area.

The introduction is also where you state your own perspective on the potential outcomes of your evaluation and analysis. Once you have hooked your reader into reading further, you can then deliver a review of relevant literature.

Review of Relevant Literature

This is an important facet of your scientific essay, because it is where you clearly explain the different perspectives in the topic area, and crucially critically examine and evaluate these views. This is vital for showing clear and logical evaluation and analysis of the facets of the problem.

Present Relevant Data and Interpretation

The next important stage is to provide evidence, either from your own research or the literature review, using factual, unbiased language, of relevant data which supports your overall arguments. It is vital in this section to ensure that you credit all your sources, and that they come from viable, credible sources and are correctly cited in text and listed in full at the end of your essay. This section should be presented in clear, separate paragraphs for each point, accompanied where appropriate with graphs or tables to support your arguments.

Once you have presented the data you need to demonstrate that you have interpreted the presented information correctly. To do this you need to relate your interpretation to the previously presented theoretical frameworks and use this relationship to support or refute your arguments for and against. When presenting your interpretation there should be a back-up from credible, viable sources, that are fully referenced at the end of your work. This phase of the essay should again be structured in the one point/one paragraph format so that your viewpoints are clear. Following on from this interpretation, there is a process of synthesis which indicates how the evidence you have gathered and presented supports the proposition you put forward in your introduction.

Once you have presented and synthesised the data, it is vital to indicate why the evidence presented refutes or confirms the major views in the topic area which you identified in the literature review. The main body of the work should then be summed up with an identification of any issues or limitations of the data you have used to reach your conclusions.

As with any essay, the conclusion should not present any new information. Instead, it should be a summation of everything presented in the essay, the arguments presented along with how your work will fit in with previous works and future assessment in the topic area.

In this section, you can include recommendations for improvement and extensions, (Note: this is not essential in all scientific essays but can lead to additional marks as it shows a recognition of the need for more research / evaluation). To help you lift your essay even further we have provided a list of key phrases that can be used to ensure your writing is scientifically appropriate and your essay is first class.

Key Phrases for a Scientific Essay

When presenting evidence:

  • It is suggested that…
  • Evidence available indicates that….
  • It has been indicated that…
  • Aspects of the work suggest that…
  • The evidence presented supports the view that…
  • The evidence presented however overlooks…
  • Closer examination suggests….
  • Evidence in support of this view can be found in the work of…

For summarising, the following phrases are useful:

  • The most important
  • First of all

When introducing clear evidence

  • There is no doubt that…
  • It is clear that…
  • From this evidence, it can be concluded that…

You may also like

How to Write an Email to a Professor

How to Write a Scientific Essay

How to write a scientific essay

When writing any essay it’s important to always keep the end goal in mind. You want to produce a document that is detailed, factual, about the subject matter and most importantly to the point.

Writing scientific essays will always be slightly different to when you write an essay for say English Literature . You need to be more analytical and precise when answering your questions. To help achieve this, you need to keep three golden rules in mind.

  • Analysing the question, so that you know exactly what you have to do

Planning your answer

  • Writing the essay

Now, let’s look at these steps in more detail to help you fully understand how to apply the three golden rules.

Analysing the question

  • Start by looking at the instruction. Essays need to be written out in continuous prose. You shouldn’t be using bullet points or writing in note form.
  • If it helps to make a particular point, however, you can use a diagram providing it is relevant and adequately explained.
  • Look at the topic you are required to write about. The wording of the essay title tells you what you should confine your answer to – there is no place for interesting facts about other areas.

The next step is to plan your answer. What we are going to try to do is show you how to produce an effective plan in a very short time. You need a framework to show your knowledge otherwise it is too easy to concentrate on only a few aspects.

For example, when writing an essay on biology we can divide the topic up in a number of different ways. So, if you have to answer a question like ‘Outline the main properties of life and system reproduction’

The steps for planning are simple. Firstly, define the main terms within the question that need to be addressed. Then list the properties asked for and lastly, roughly assess how many words of your word count you are going to allocate to each term.

Writing the Essay

The final step (you’re almost there), now you have your plan in place for the essay, it’s time to get it all down in black and white. Follow your plan for answering the question, making sure you stick to the word count, check your spelling and grammar and give credit where credit’s (always reference your sources).

How Tutors Breakdown Essays

An exceptional essay

  • reflects the detail that could be expected from a comprehensive knowledge and understanding of relevant parts of the specification
  • is free from fundamental errors
  • maintains appropriate depth and accuracy throughout
  • includes two or more paragraphs of material that indicates greater depth or breadth of study

A good essay

An average essay

  • contains a significant amount of material that reflects the detail that could be expected from a knowledge and understanding of relevant parts of the specification.

In practice this will amount to about half the essay.

  • is likely to reflect limited knowledge of some areas and to be patchy in quality
  • demonstrates a good understanding of basic principles with some errors and evidence of misunderstanding

A poor essay

  • contains much material which is below the level expected of a candidate who has completed the course
  • Contains fundamental errors reflecting a poor grasp of basic principles and concepts

essay model science

Privacy Overview

CookieDurationDescription
cookielawinfo-checkbox-analytics11 monthsThis cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Analytics".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-functional11 monthsThe cookie is set by GDPR cookie consent to record the user consent for the cookies in the category "Functional".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-necessary11 monthsThis cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookies is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Necessary".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-others11 monthsThis cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Other.
cookielawinfo-checkbox-performance11 monthsThis cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Performance".
viewed_cookie_policy11 monthsThe cookie is set by the GDPR Cookie Consent plugin and is used to store whether or not user has consented to the use of cookies. It does not store any personal data.

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Models in Science

Models are of central importance in many scientific contexts. The centrality of models such as inflationary models in cosmology, general-circulation models of the global climate, the double-helix model of DNA, evolutionary models in biology, agent-based models in the social sciences, and general-equilibrium models of markets in their respective domains is a case in point (the Other Internet Resources section at the end of this entry contains links to online resources that discuss these models). Scientists spend significant amounts of time building, testing, comparing, and revising models, and much journal space is dedicated to interpreting and discussing the implications of models.

As a result, models have attracted philosophers’ attention and there are now sizable bodies of literature about various aspects of scientific modeling. A tangible result of philosophical engagement with models is a proliferation of model types recognized in the philosophical literature. Probing models , phenomenological models , computational models , developmental models , explanatory models , impoverished models , testing models , idealized models , theoretical models , scale models , heuristic models , caricature models , exploratory models , didactic models , fantasy models , minimal models , toy models , imaginary models , mathematical models , mechanistic models , substitute models , iconic models , formal models , analogue models , and instrumental models are but some of the notions that are used to categorize models. While at first glance this abundance is overwhelming, it can be brought under control by recognizing that these notions pertain to different problems that arise in connection with models. Models raise questions in semantics (how, if at all, do models represent?), ontology (what kind of things are models?), epistemology (how do we learn and explain with models?), and, of course, in other domains within philosophy of science.

1. Semantics: Models and Representation

2.1 physical objects, 2.2 fictional objects and abstract objects, 2.3 set-theoretic structures, 2.4 descriptions and equations, 3.1 learning about models, 3.2 learning about target systems, 3.3 explaining with models, 3.4 understanding with models, 3.5 other cognitive functions, 4.1 models as subsidiaries to theory, 4.2 models as independent from theories, 5.1 models, realism, and laws of nature, 5.2 models and reductionism, other internet resources, related entries.

Many scientific models are representational models: they represent a selected part or aspect of the world, which is the model’s target system. Standard examples are the billiard ball model of a gas, the Bohr model of the atom, the Lotka–Volterra model of predator–prey interaction, the Mundell–Fleming model of an open economy, and the scale model of a bridge.

This raises the question what it means for a model to represent a target system. This problem is rather involved and decomposes into various subproblems. For an in-depth discussion of the issue of representation, see the entry on scientific representation . At this point, rather than addressing the issue of what it means for a model to represent, we focus on a number of different kinds of representation that play important roles in the practice of model-based science, namely scale models, analogical models, idealized models, toy models, minimal models, phenomenological models, exploratory models, and models of data. These categories are not mutually exclusive, and a given model can fall into several categories at once.

Scale models . Some models are down-sized or enlarged copies of their target systems (Black 1962). A typical example is a small wooden car that is put into a wind tunnel to explore the actual car’s aerodynamic properties. The intuition is that a scale model is a naturalistic replica or a truthful mirror image of the target; for this reason, scale models are sometimes also referred to as “true models” (Achinstein 1968: Ch. 7). However, there is no such thing as a perfectly faithful scale model; faithfulness is always restricted to some respects. The wooden scale model of the car provides a faithful portrayal of the car’s shape but not of its material. And even in the respects in which a model is a faithful representation, the relation between model-properties and target-properties is usually not straightforward. When engineers use, say, a 1:100 scale model of a ship to investigate the resistance that an actual ship experiences when moving through the water, they cannot simply measure the resistance the model experiences and then multiply it with the scale. In fact, the resistance faced by the model does not translate into the resistance faced by the actual ship in a straightforward manner (that is, one cannot simply scale the water resistance with the scale of the model: the real ship need not have one hundred times the water resistance of its 1:100 model). The two quantities stand in a complicated nonlinear relation with each other, and the exact form of that relation is often highly nontrivial and emerges as the result of a thoroughgoing study of the situation (Sterrett 2006, forthcoming; Pincock forthcoming).

Analogical models . Standard examples of analogical models include the billiard ball model of a gas, the hydraulic model of an economic system, and the dumb hole model of a black hole. At the most basic level, two things are analogous if there are certain relevant similarities between them. In a classic text, Hesse (1963) distinguishes different types of analogies according to the kinds of similarity relations into which two objects enter. A simple type of analogy is one that is based on shared properties. There is an analogy between the earth and the moon based on the fact that both are large, solid, opaque, spherical bodies that receive heat and light from the sun, revolve around their axes, and gravitate towards other bodies. But sameness of properties is not a necessary condition. An analogy between two objects can also be based on relevant similarities between their properties. In this more liberal sense, we can say that there is an analogy between sound and light because echoes are similar to reflections, loudness to brightness, pitch to color, detectability by the ear to detectability by the eye, and so on.

Analogies can also be based on the sameness or resemblance of relations between parts of two systems rather than on their monadic properties. It is in this sense that the relation of a father to his children is asserted to be analogous to the relation of the state to its citizens. The analogies mentioned so far have been what Hesse calls “material analogies”. We obtain a more formal notion of analogy when we abstract from the concrete features of the systems and only focus on their formal set-up. What the analogue model then shares with its target is not a set of features, but the same pattern of abstract relationships (i.e., the same structure, where structure is understood in a formal sense). This notion of analogy is closely related to what Hesse calls “formal analogy”. Two items are related by formal analogy if they are both interpretations of the same formal calculus. For instance, there is a formal analogy between a swinging pendulum and an oscillating electric circuit because they are both described by the same mathematical equation.

A further important distinction due to Hesse is the one between positive, negative, and neutral analogies. The positive analogy between two items consists in the properties or relations they share (both gas molecules and billiard balls have mass); the negative analogy consists in the properties they do not share (billiard balls are colored, gas molecules are not); the neutral analogy comprises the properties of which it is not known (yet) whether they belong to the positive or the negative analogy (do billiard balls and molecules have the same cross section in scattering processes?). Neutral analogies play an important role in scientific research because they give rise to questions and suggest new hypotheses. For this reason several authors have emphasized the heuristic role that analogies play in theory and model construction, as well as in creative thought (Bailer-Jones and Bailer-Jones 2002; Bailer-Jones 2009: Ch. 3; Hesse 1974; Holyoak and Thagard 1995; Kroes 1989; Psillos 1995; and the essays collected in Helman 1988). See also the entry on analogy and analogical reasoning .

It has also been discussed whether using analogical models can in some cases be confirmatory in a Bayesian sense. Hesse (1974: 208–219) argues that this is possible if the analogy is a material analogy. Bartha (2010, 2013 [2019]) disagrees and argues that analogical models cannot be confirmatory in a Bayesian sense because the information encapsulated in an analogical model is part of the relevant background knowledge, which has the consequence that the posterior probability of a hypothesis about a target system cannot change as a result of observing the analogy. Analogical models can therefore only establish the plausibility of a conclusion in the sense of justifying a non-negligible prior probability assignment (Bartha 2010: §8.5).

More recently, these questions have been discussed in the context of so-called analogue experiments, which promise to provide knowledge about an experimentally inaccessible target system (e.g., a black hole) by manipulating another system, the source system (e.g., a Bose–Einstein condensate). Dardashti, Thébault, and Winsberg (2017) and Dardashti, Hartmann et al. (2019) have argued that, given certain conditions, an analogue simulation of one system by another system can confirm claims about the target system (e.g., that black holes emit Hawking radiation). See Crowther et al. (forthcoming) for a critical discussion, and also the entry on computer simulations in science .

Idealized models . Idealized models are models that involve a deliberate simplification or distortion of something complicated with the objective of making it more tractable or understandable. Frictionless planes, point masses, completely isolated systems, omniscient and fully rational agents, and markets in perfect equilibrium are well-known examples. Idealizations are a crucial means for science to cope with systems that are too difficult to study in their full complexity (Potochnik 2017).

Philosophical debates over idealization have focused on two general kinds of idealizations: so-called Aristotelian and Galilean idealizations. Aristotelian idealization amounts to “stripping away”, in our imagination, all properties from a concrete object that we believe are not relevant to the problem at hand. There is disagreement on how this is done. Jones (2005) and Godfrey-Smith (2009) offer an analysis of abstraction in terms of truth: while an abstraction remains silent about certain features or aspects of the system, it does not say anything false and still offers a true (albeit restricted) description. This allows scientists to focus on a limited set of properties in isolation. An example is a classical-mechanics model of the planetary system, which describes the position of an object as a function of time and disregards all other properties of planets. Cartwright (1989: Ch. 5), Musgrave (1981), who uses the term “negligibility assumptions”, and Mäki (1994), who speaks of the “method of isolation”, allow abstractions to say something false, for instance by neglecting a causally relevant factor.

Galilean idealizations are ones that involve deliberate distortions: physicists build models consisting of point masses moving on frictionless planes; economists assume that agents are omniscient; biologists study isolated populations; and so on. Using simplifications of this sort whenever a situation is too difficult to tackle was characteristic of Galileo’s approach to science. For this reason it is common to refer to ‘distortive’ idealizations of this kind as “Galilean idealizations” (McMullin 1985). An example for such an idealization is a model of motion on an ice rink that assumes the ice to be frictionless, when, in reality, it has low but non-zero friction.

Galilean idealizations are sometimes characterized as controlled idealizations, i.e., as ones that allow for de-idealization by successive removal of the distorting assumptions (McMullin 1985; Weisberg 2007). Thus construed, Galilean idealizations don’t cover all distortive idealizations. Batterman (2002, 2011) and Rice (2015, 2019) discuss distortive idealizations that are ineliminable in that they cannot be removed from the model without dismantling the model altogether.

What does a model involving distortions tell us about reality? Laymon (1991) formulated a theory which understands idealizations as ideal limits: imagine a series of refinements of the actual situation which approach the postulated limit, and then require that the closer the properties of a system come to the ideal limit, the closer its behavior has to come to the behavior of the system at the limit (monotonicity). If this is the case, then scientists can study the system at the limit and carry over conclusions from that system to systems distant from the limit. But these conditions need not always hold. In fact, it can happen that the limiting system does not approach the system at the limit. If this happens, we are faced with a singular limit (Berry 2002). In such cases the system at the limit can exhibit behavior that is different from the behavior of systems distant from the limit. Limits of this kind appear in a number of contexts, most notably in the theory of phase transitions in statistical mechanics. There is, however, no agreement over the correct interpretation of such limits. Batterman (2002, 2011) sees them as indicative of emergent phenomena, while Butterfield (2011a,b) sees them as compatible with reduction (see also the entries on intertheory relations in physics and scientific reduction ).

Galilean and Aristotelian idealizations are not mutually exclusive, and many models exhibit both in that they take into account a narrow set of properties and distort them. Consider again the classical-mechanics model of the planetary system: the model only takes a narrow set of properties into account and distorts them, for instance by describing planets as ideal spheres with a rotation-symmetric mass distribution.

A concept that is closely related to idealization is approximation. In a broad sense, A can be called an approximation of B if A is somehow close to B . This, however, is too broad because it makes room for any likeness to qualify as an approximation. Rueger and Sharp (1998) limit approximations to quantitative closeness, and Portides (2007) frames it as an essentially mathematical concept. On that notion A is an approximation of B iff A is close to B in a specifiable mathematical sense, where the relevant sense of “close” will be given by the context. An example is the approximation of one curve with another one, which can be achieved by expanding a function into a power series and only keeping the first two or three terms. In different situations we approximate an equation with another one by letting a control parameter tend towards zero (Redhead 1980). This raises the question of how approximations are different from idealizations, which can also involve mathematical closeness. Norton (2012) sees the distinction between the two as referential: an approximation is an inexact description of the target while an idealization introduces a secondary system (real or fictitious) which stands for the target system (while being distinct from it). If we say that the period of the pendulum on the wall is roughly two seconds, then this is an approximation; if we reason about the real pendulum by assuming that the pendulum bob is a point mass and that the string is massless (i.e., if we assume that the pendulum is a so-called ideal pendulum), then we use an idealization. Separating idealizations and approximations in this way does not imply that there cannot be interesting relations between the two. For instance, an approximation can be justified by pointing out that it is the mathematical expression of an acceptable idealization (e.g., when we neglect a dissipative term in an equation of motion because we make the idealizing assumption that the system is frictionless).

Toy models . Toy models are extremely simplified and strongly distorted renderings of their targets, and often only represent a small number of causal or explanatory factors (Hartmann 1995; Reutlinger et al. 2018; Nguyen forthcoming). Typical examples are the Lotka–Volterra model in population ecology (Weisberg 2013) and the Schelling model of segregation in the social sciences (Sugden 2000). Toy models usually do not perform well in terms of prediction and empirical adequacy, and they seem to serve other epistemic goals (more on these in Section 3 ). This raises the question whether they should be regarded as representational at all (Luczak 2017).

Some toy models are characterized as “caricatures” (Gibbard and Varian 1978; Batterman and Rice 2014). Caricature models isolate a small number of salient characteristics of a system and distort them into an extreme case. A classic example is Akerlof’s (1970) model of the car market (“the market for lemons”), which explains the difference in price between new and used cars solely in terms of asymmetric information, thereby disregarding all other factors that may influence the prices of cars (see also Sugden 2000). However, it is controversial whether such highly idealized models can still be regarded as informative representations of their target systems. For a discussion of caricature models, in particular in economics, see Reiss (2006).

Minimal models . Minimal models are closely related to toy models in that they are also highly simplified. They are so simplified that some argue that they are non-representational: they lack any similarity, isomorphism, or resemblance relation to the world (Batterman and Rice 2014). It has been argued that many economic models are of this kind (Grüne-Yanoff 2009). Minimal economic models are also unconstrained by natural laws, and do not isolate any real factors ( ibid .). And yet, minimal models help us to learn something about the world in the sense that they function as surrogates for a real system: scientists can study the model to learn something about the target. It is, however, controversial whether minimal models can assist scientists in learning something about the world if they do not represent anything (Fumagalli 2016). Minimal models that purportedly lack any similarity or representation are also used in different parts of physics to explain the macro-scale behavior of various systems whose micro-scale behavior is extremely diverse (Batterman and Rice 2014; Rice 2018, 2019; Shech 2018). Typical examples are the features of phase transitions and the flow of fluids. Proponents of minimal models argue that what provides an explanation of the macro-scale behavior of a system in these cases is not a feature that system and model have in common, but the fact that the system and the model belong to the same universality class (a class of models that exhibit the same limiting behavior even though they show very different behavior at finite scales). It is, however, controversial whether explanations of this kind are possible without reference to at least some common features (Lange 2015; Reutlinger 2017).

Phenomenological models . Phenomenological models have been defined in different, although related, ways. A common definition takes them to be models that only represent observable properties of their targets and refrain from postulating hidden mechanisms and the like (Bokulich 2011). Another approach, due to McMullin (1968), defines phenomenological models as models that are independent of theories. This, however, seems to be too strong. Many phenomenological models, while failing to be derivable from a theory, incorporate principles and laws associated with theories. The liquid-drop model of the atomic nucleus, for instance, portrays the nucleus as a liquid drop and describes it as having several properties (surface tension and charge, among others) originating in different theories (hydrodynamics and electrodynamics, respectively). Certain aspects of these theories—although usually not the full theories—are then used to determine both the static and dynamical properties of the nucleus. Finally, it is tempting to identify phenomenological models with models of a phenomenon . Here, “phenomenon” is an umbrella term covering all relatively stable and general features of the world that are interesting from a scientific point of view. The weakening of sound as a function of the distance to the source, the decay of alpha particles, the chemical reactions that take place when a piece of limestone dissolves in an acid, the growth of a population of rabbits, and the dependence of house prices on the base rate of the Federal Reserve are phenomena in this sense. For further discussion, see Bailer-Jones (2009: Ch. 7), Bogen and Woodward (1988), and the entry on theory and observation in science .

Exploratory models . Exploratory models are models which are not proposed in the first place to learn something about a specific target system or a particular experimentally established phenomenon. Exploratory models function as the starting point of further explorations in which the model is modified and refined. Gelfert (2016) points out that exploratory models can provide proofs-of-principle and suggest how-possibly explanations (2016: Ch. 4). As an example, Gelfert mentions early models in theoretical ecology, such as the Lotka–Volterra model of predator–prey interaction, which mimic the qualitative behavior of speed-up and slow-down in population growth in an environment with limited resources (2016: 80). Such models do not give an accurate account of the behavior of any actual population, but they provide the starting point for the development of more realistic models. Massimi (2019) notes that exploratory models provide modal knowledge. Fisher (2006) sees these models as tools for the examination of the features of a given theory.

Models of data. A model of data (sometimes also “data model”) is a corrected, rectified, regimented, and in many instances idealized version of the data we gain from immediate observation, the so-called raw data (Suppes 1962). Characteristically, one first eliminates errors (e.g., removes points from the record that are due to faulty observation) and then presents the data in a “neat” way, for instance by drawing a smooth curve through a set of points. These two steps are commonly referred to as “data reduction” and “curve fitting”. When we investigate, for instance, the trajectory of a certain planet, we first eliminate points that are fallacious from the observation records and then fit a smooth curve to the remaining ones. Models of data play a crucial role in confirming theories because it is the model of data, and not the often messy and complex raw data, that theories are tested against.

The construction of a model of data can be extremely complicated. It requires sophisticated statistical techniques and raises serious methodological as well as philosophical questions. How do we decide which points on the record need to be removed? And given a clean set of data, what curve do we fit to it? The first question has been dealt with mainly within the context of the philosophy of experiment (see, for instance, Galison 1997 and Staley 2004). At the heart of the latter question lies the so-called curve-fitting problem, which is that the data themselves dictate neither the form of the fitted curve nor what statistical techniques scientists should use to construct a curve. The choice and rationalization of statistical techniques is the subject matter of the philosophy of statistics, and we refer the reader to the entry Philosophy of Statistics and to Bandyopadhyay and Forster (2011) for a discussion of these issues. Further discussions of models of data can be found in Bailer-Jones (2009: Ch. 7), Brewer and Chinn (1994), Harris (2003), Hartmann (1995), Laymon (1982), Mayo (1996, 2018), and Suppes (2007).

The gathering, processing, dissemination, analysis, interpretation, and storage of data raise many important questions beyond the relatively narrow issues pertaining to models of data. Leonelli (2016, 2019) investigates the status of data in science, argues that data should be defined not by their provenance but by their evidential function, and studies how data travel between different contexts.

2. Ontology: What Are Models?

What are models? That is, what kind of object are scientists dealing with when they work with a model? A number of authors have voiced skepticism that this question has a meaningful answer, because models do not belong to a distinctive ontological category and anything can be a model (Callender and Cohen 2006; Giere 2010; Suárez 2004; Swoyer 1991; Teller 2001). Contessa (2010) replies that this is a non sequitur . Even if, from an ontological point of view, anything can be a model and the class of things that are referred to as models contains a heterogeneous collection of different things, it does not follow that it is either impossible or pointless to develop an ontology of models. This is because even if not all models are of a particular ontological kind, one can nevertheless ask to what ontological kinds the things that are de facto used as models belong. There may be several such kinds and each kind can be analyzed in its own right. What sort of objects scientists use as models has important repercussions for how models perform relevant functions such as representation and explanation, and hence this issue cannot be dismissed as “just sociology”.

The objects that commonly serve as models indeed belong to different ontological kinds: physical objects, fictional objects, abstract objects, set-theoretic structures, descriptions, equations, or combinations of some of these, are frequently referred to as models, and some models may fall into yet other classes of things. Following Contessa’s advice, the aim then is to develop an ontology for each of these. Those with an interest in ontology may see this as a goal in its own right. It pays noting, however, that the question has reverberations beyond ontology and bears on how one understands the semantics and the epistemology of models.

Some models are physical objects. Such models are commonly referred to as “material models”. Standard examples of models of this kind are scale models of objects like bridges and ships (see Section 1 ), Watson and Crick’s metal model of DNA (Schaffner 1969), Phillips and Newlyn’s hydraulic model of an economy (Morgan and Boumans 2004), the US Army Corps of Engineers’ model of the San Francisco Bay (Weisberg 2013), Kendrew’s plasticine model of myoglobin (Frigg and Nguyen 2016), and model organisms in the life sciences (Leonelli and Ankeny 2012; Leonelli 2010; Levy and Currie 2015). All these are material objects that serve as models. Material models do not give rise to ontological difficulties over and above the well-known problems in connection with objects that metaphysicians deal with, for instance concerning the nature of properties, the identity of objects, parts and wholes, and so on.

However, many models are not material models. The Bohr model of the atom, a frictionless pendulum, or an isolated population, for instance, are in the scientist’s mind rather than in the laboratory and they do not have to be physically realized and experimented upon to serve as models. These “non-physical” models raise serious ontological questions, and how they are best analyzed is debated controversially. In the remainder of this section we review some of the suggestions that have attracted attention in the recent literature on models.

What has become known as the fiction view of models sees models as akin to the imagined objects of literary fiction—that is, as akin to fictional characters like Sherlock Holmes or fictional places like Middle Earth (Godfrey-Smith 2007). So when Bohr introduced his model of the atom he introduced a fictional object of the same kind as the object Conan Doyle introduced when he invented Sherlock Holmes. This view squares well with scientific practice, where scientists often talk about models as if they were objects and often take themselves to be describing imaginary atoms, populations, or economies. It also squares well with philosophical views that see the construction and manipulation of models as essential aspects of scientific investigation (Morgan 1999), even if models are not material objects, because these practices seem to be directed toward some kind of object.

What philosophical questions does this move solve? Fictional discourse and fictional entities face well-known philosophical questions, and one may well argue that simply likening models to fictions amounts to explaining obscurum per obscurius (for a discussion of these questions, see the entry on fictional entities ). One way to counter this objection and to motivate the fiction view of models is to point to the view’s heuristic power. In this vein Frigg (2010b) identifies five specific issues that an ontology of models has to address and then notes that these issues arise in very similar ways in the discussion about fiction (the issues are the identity conditions, property attribution, the semantics of comparative statements, truth conditions, and the epistemology of imagined objects). Likening models to fiction then has heuristic value because there is a rich literature on fiction that offers a number of solutions to these issues.

Only a small portion of the options available in the extensive literature on fictions have actually been explored in the context of scientific models. Contessa (2010) formulates what he calls the “dualist account”, according to which a model is an abstract object that stands for a possible concrete object. The Rutherford model of the atom, for instance, is an abstract object that acts as a stand-in for one of the possible systems that contain an electron orbiting around a nucleus in a well-defined orbit. Barberousse and Ludwig (2009) and Frigg (2010b) take a different route and develop an account of models as fictions based on Walton’s (1990) pretense theory of fiction. According to this view the sentences of a passage of text introducing a model should be seen as a prop in a game of make-believe, and the model is the product of an act of pretense. This is an antirealist position in that it takes talk of model “objects” to be figures of speech because ultimately there are no model objects—models only live in scientists’ imaginations. Salis (forthcoming) reformulates this view to become what she calls the “the new fiction view of models”. The core difference lies in the fact that what is considered as the model are the model descriptions and their content rather than the imaginings that they prescribe. This is a realist view of models, because descriptions exist.

The fiction view is not without critics. Giere (2009), Magnani (2012), Pincock (2012), Portides (2014), and Teller (2009) reject the fiction approach and argue, in different ways, that models should not be regarded as fictions. Weisberg (2013) argues for a middle position which sees fictions as playing a heuristic role but denies that they should be regarded as forming part of a scientific model. The common core of these criticisms is that the fiction view misconstrues the epistemic standing of models. To call something a fiction, so the charge goes, is tantamount to saying that it is false, and it is unjustified to call an entire model a fiction—and thereby claim that it fails to capture how the world is—just because the model involves certain false assumptions or fictional elements. In other words, a representation isn’t automatically counted as fiction just because it has some inaccuracies. Proponents of the fiction view agree with this point but deny that the notion of fiction should be analyzed in terms of falsity. What makes a work a fiction is not its falsity (or some ratio of false to true claims): neither is everything that is said in a novel untrue (Tolstoy’s War and Peace contains many true statements about Napoleon’s Franco-Russian War), nor does every text containing false claims qualify as fiction (false news reports are just that, they are not fictions). The defining feature of a fiction is that readers are supposed to imagine the events and characters described, not that they are false (Frigg 2010a; Salis forthcoming).

Giere (1988) advocated the view that “non-physical” models are abstract entities. However, there is little agreement on the nature of abstract objects, and Hale (1988: 86–87) lists no less than twelve different possible characterizations (for a review of the available options, see the entry on abstract objects ). In recent publications, Thomasson (2020) and Thomson-Jones (2020) develop what they call an “artifactualist view” of models, which is based on Thomasson’s (1999) theory of abstract artifacts. This view agrees with the pretense theory that the content of text that introduces a fictional character or a model should be understood as occurring in pretense, but at the same time insists that in producing such descriptions authors create abstract cultural artifacts that then exist independently of either the author or the readers. Artifactualism agrees with Platonism that abstract objects exist, but insists, contra Platonism, that abstract objects are brought into existence through a creative act and are not eternal. This allows the artifactualist to preserve the advantages of pretense theory while at the same time holding the realist view that fictional characters and models actually exist.

An influential point of view takes models to be set-theoretic structures. This position can be traced back to Suppes (1960) and is now, with slight variants, held by most proponents of the so-called semantic view of theories (for a discussion of this view, see the entry on the structure of scientific theories ). There are differences between the versions of the semantic view, but with the exception of Giere (1988) all versions agree that models are structures of one sort or another (Da Costa and French 2000).

This view of models has been criticized on various grounds. One pervasive criticism is that many types of models that play an important role in science are not structures and cannot be accommodated within the structuralist view of models, which can neither account for how these models are constructed nor for how they work in the context of investigation (Cartwright 1999; Downes 1992; Morrison 1999). Examples for such models are interpretative models and mediating models, discussed later in Section 4.2 . Another charge held against the set-theoretic approach is that set-theoretic structures by themselves cannot be representational models—at least if that requires them to share some structure with the target—because the ascription of a structure to a target system which forms part of the physical world relies on a substantive (non-structural) description of the target, which goes beyond what the structuralist approach can afford (Nguyen and Frigg forthcoming).

A time-honored position has it that a model is a stylized description of a target system. It has been argued that this is what scientists display in papers and textbooks when they present a model (Achinstein 1968; Black 1962). This view has not been subject to explicit criticism. However, some of the criticisms that have been marshaled against the so-called syntactic view of theories equally threaten a linguistic understanding of models (for a discussion of this view, see the entry on the structure of scientific theories ). First, a standard criticism of the syntactic view is that by associating a theory with a particular formulation, the view misconstrues theory identity because any change in the formulation results in a new theory (Suppe 2000). A view that associates models with descriptions would seem to be open to the same criticism. Second, models have different properties than descriptions: the Newtonian model of the solar system consists of orbiting spheres, but it makes no sense to say this about its description. Conversely, descriptions have properties that models do not have: a description can be written in English and consist of 517 words, but the same cannot be said of a model. One way around these difficulties is to associate the model with the content of a description rather than with the description itself. For a discussion of a position on models that builds on the content of a description, see Salis (forthcoming).

A contemporary version of descriptivism is Levy’s (2012, 2015) and Toon’s (2012) so-called direct-representation view. This view shares with the fiction view of models ( Section 2.2 ) the reliance on Walton’s pretense theory, but uses it in a different way. The main difference is that the views discussed earlier see modeling as introducing a vehicle of representation, the model, that is distinct from the target, and they see the problem as elucidating what kind of thing the model is. On the direct-representation view there are no models distinct from the target; there are only model-descriptions and targets, with no models in-between them. Modeling, on this view, consists in providing an imaginative description of real things. A model-description prescribes imaginings about the real system; the ideal pendulum, for instance, prescribes model-users to imagine the real spring as perfectly elastic and the bob as a point mass. This approach avoids the above problems because the identity conditions for models are given by the conditions for games of make-believe (and not by the syntax of a description) and property ascriptions take place in pretense. There are, however, questions about how this account deals with models that have no target (like models of the ether or four-sex populations), and about how models thus understood deal with idealizations. For a discussion of these points, see Frigg and Nguyen (2016), Poznic (2016), and Salis (forthcoming).

A closely related approach sees models as equations. This is a version of the view that models are descriptions, because equations are syntactic items that describe a mathematical structure. The issues that this view faces are similar to the ones we have already encountered: First, one can describe the same situation using different kinds of coordinates and as a result obtain different equations but without thereby also obtaining a different model. Second, the model and the equation have different properties. A pendulum contains a massless string, but the equation describing its motion does not; and an equation may be inhomogeneous, but the system it describes is not. It is an open question whether these issues can be avoided by appeal to a pretense account.

3. Epistemology: The Cognitive Functions of Models

One of the main reasons why models play such an important role in science is that they perform a number of cognitive functions. For example, models are vehicles for learning about the world. Significant parts of scientific investigation are carried out on models rather than on reality itself because by studying a model we can discover features of, and ascertain facts about, the system the model stands for: models allow for “surrogative reasoning” (Swoyer 1991). For instance, we study the nature of the hydrogen atom, the dynamics of a population, or the behavior of a polymer by studying their respective models. This cognitive function of models has been widely acknowledged in the literature, and some even suggest that models give rise to a new style of reasoning, “model-based reasoning”, according to which “inferences are made by means of creating models and manipulating, adapting, and evaluating them” (Nersessian 2010: 12; see also Magnani, Nersessian, and Thagard 1999; Magnani and Nersessian 2002; and Magnani and Casadio 2016).

Learning about a model happens in two places: in the construction of the model and in its manipulation (Morgan 1999). There are no fixed rules or recipes for model building and so the very activity of figuring out what fits together, and how, affords an opportunity to learn about the model. Once the model is built, we do not learn about its properties by looking at it; we have to use and manipulate the model in order to elicit its secrets.

Depending on what kind of model we are dealing with, building and manipulating a model amount to different activities demanding different methodologies. Material models seem to be straightforward because they are used in common experimental contexts (e.g., we put the model of a car in the wind tunnel and measure its air resistance). Hence, as far as learning about the model is concerned, material models do not give rise to questions that go beyond questions concerning experimentation more generally.

Not so with fictional and abstract models. What constraints are there to the construction of fictional and abstract models, and how do we manipulate them? A natural response seems to be that we do this by performing a thought experiment. Different authors (e.g., Brown 1991; Gendler 2000; Norton 1991; Reiss 2003; Sorensen 1992) have explored this line of argument, but they have reached very different and often conflicting conclusions about how thought experiments are performed and what the status of their outcomes is (for details, see the entry on thought experiments ).

An important class of models is computational in nature. For some models it is possible to derive results or solve equations of a mathematical model analytically. But quite often this is not the case. It is at this point that computers have a great impact, because they allow us to solve problems that are otherwise intractable. Hence, computational methods provide us with knowledge about (the consequences of) a model where analytical methods remain silent. Many parts of current research in both the natural and social sciences rely on computer simulations, which help scientists to explore the consequences of models that cannot be investigated otherwise. The formation and development of stars and galaxies, the dynamics of high-energy heavy-ion reactions, the evolution of life, outbreaks of wars, the progression of an economy, moral behavior, and the consequences of decision procedures in an organization are explored with computer simulations, to mention only a few examples.

Computer simulations are also heuristically important. They can suggest new theories, models, and hypotheses, for example, based on a systematic exploration of a model’s parameter space (Hartmann 1996). But computer simulations also bear methodological perils. For example, they may provide misleading results because, due to the discrete nature of the calculations carried out on a digital computer, they only allow for the exploration of a part of the full parameter space, and this subspace need not reflect every important feature of the model. The severity of this problem is somewhat mitigated by the increasing power of modern computers. But the availability of more computational power can also have adverse effects: it may encourage scientists to swiftly come up with increasingly complex but conceptually premature models, involving poorly understood assumptions or mechanisms and too many additional adjustable parameters (for a discussion of a related problem in the social sciences, see Braun and Saam 2015: Ch. 3). This can lead to an increase in empirical adequacy—which may be welcome for certain forecasting tasks—but not necessarily to a better understanding of the underlying mechanisms. As a result, the use of computer simulations can change the weight we assign to the various goals of science. Finally, the availability of computer power may seduce scientists into making calculations that do not have the degree of trustworthiness one would expect them to have. This happens, for instance, when computers are used to propagate probability distributions forward in time, which can turn out to be misleading (see Frigg et al. 2014). So it is important not to be carried away by the means that new powerful computers offer and lose sight of the actual goals of research. For a discussion of further issues in connection with computer simulations, we refer the reader to the entry on computer simulations in science .

Once we have knowledge about the model, this knowledge has to be “translated” into knowledge about the target system. It is at this point that the representational function of models becomes important again: if a model represents, then it can instruct us about reality because (at least some of) the model’s parts or aspects have corresponding parts or aspects in the world. But if learning is connected to representation and if there are different kinds of representations (analogies, idealizations, etc.), then there are also different kinds of learning. If, for instance, we have a model we take to be a realistic depiction, the transfer of knowledge from the model to the target is accomplished in a different manner than when we deal with an analogue, or a model that involves idealizing assumptions. For a discussion of the different ways in which the representational function of models can be exploited to learn about the target, we refer the reader to the entry Scientific Representation .

Some models explain. But how can they fulfill this function given that they typically involve idealizations? Do these models explain despite or because of the idealizations they involve? Does an explanatory use of models presuppose that they represent, or can non-representational models also explain? And what kind of explanation do models provide?

There is a long tradition requesting that the explanans of a scientific explanation must be true. We find this requirement in the deductive-nomological model (Hempel 1965) as well as in the more recent literature. For instance, Strevens (2008: 297) claims that “no causal account of explanation … allows nonveridical models to explain”. For further discussions, see also Colombo et al. (2015).

Authors working in this tradition deny that idealizations make a positive contribution to explanation and explore how models can explain despite being idealized. McMullin (1968, 1985) argues that a causal explanation based on an idealized model leaves out only features which are irrelevant for the respective explanatory task (see also Salmon 1984 and Piccinini and Craver 2011 for a discussion of mechanism sketches). Friedman (1974) argues that a more realistic (and hence less idealized) model explains better on the unification account. The idea is that idealizations can (at least in principle) be de-idealized (for a critical discussion of this claim in the context of the debate about scientific explanations, see Batterman 2002; Bokulich 2011; Morrison 2005, 2009; Jebeile and Kennedy 2015; and Rice 2015). Strevens (2008) argues that an explanatory causal model has to provide an accurate representation of the relevant causal relationships or processes which the model shares with the target system. The idealized assumptions of a model do not make a difference for the phenomenon under consideration and are therefore explanatorily irrelevant. In contrast, both Potochnik (2017) and Rice (2015) argue that models that explain can directly distort many difference-making causes.

According to Woodward’s (2003) theory, models are tools to find out about the causal relations that hold between certain facts or processes, and it is these relations that do the explanatory work. More specifically, explanations provide information about patterns of counterfactual dependence between the explanans and the explanandum which

enable us to see what sort of difference it would have made for the explanandum if the factors cited in the explanans had been different in various possible ways. (Woodward 2003: 11)

Accounts of causal explanation have also led to various claims about how idealized models can provide explanations, exploring to what extent idealization allows for the misrepresentation of irrelevant causal factors by the explanatory model (Elgin and Sober 2002; Strevens 2004, 2008; Potochnik 2007; Weisberg 2007, 2013). However, having the causally relevant features in common with real systems continues to play the essential role in showing how idealized models can be explanatory.

But is it really the truth of the explanans that makes the model explanatory? Other authors pursue a more radical line and argue that false models explain not only despite their falsity, but in fact because of their falsity. Cartwright (1983: 44) maintains that “the truth doesn’t explain much”. In her so-called “simulacrum account of explanation”, she suggests that we explain a phenomenon by constructing a model that fits the phenomenon into the basic framework of a grand theory (1983: Ch. 8). On this account, the model itself is the explanation we seek. This squares well with basic scientific intuitions, but it leaves us with the question of what notion of explanation is at work (see also Elgin and Sober 2002) and of what explanatory function idealizations play in model explanations (Rice 2018, 2019). Wimsatt (2007: Ch. 6) stresses the role of false models as means to arrive at true theories. Batterman and Rice (2014) argue that models explain because the details that characterize specific systems do not matter for the explanation. Bokulich (2008, 2009, 2011, 2012) pursues a similar line of reasoning and sees the explanatory power of models as being closely related to their fictional nature. Bokulich (2009) and Kennedy (2012) present non-representational accounts of model explanation (see also Jebeile and Kennedy 2015). Reiss (2012) and Woody (2004) provide general discussions of the relationship between representation and explanation.

Many authors have pointed out that understanding is one of the central goals of science (see, for instance, de Regt 2017; Elgin 2017; Khalifa 2017; Potochnik 2017). In some cases, we want to understand a certain phenomenon (e.g., why the sky is blue); in other cases, we want to understand a specific scientific theory (e.g., quantum mechanics) that accounts for a phenomenon in question. Sometimes we gain understanding of a phenomenon by understanding the corresponding theory or model. For instance, Maxwell’s theory of electromagnetism helps us understand why the sky is blue. It is, however, controversial whether understanding a phenomenon always presupposes an understanding of the corresponding theory (de Regt 2009: 26).

Although there are many different ways of gaining understanding, models and the activity of scientific modeling are of particular importance here (de Regt et al. 2009; Morrison 2009; Potochnik 2017; Rice 2016). This insight can be traced back at least to Lord Kelvin who, in his famous 1884 Baltimore Lectures on Molecular Dynamics and the Wave Theory of Light , maintained that “the test of ‘Do we or do we not understand a particular subject in physics?’ is ‘Can we make a mechanical model of it?’” (Kelvin 1884 [1987: 111]; see also Bailer-Jones 2009: Ch. 2; and de Regt 2017: Ch. 6).

But why do models play such a crucial role in the understanding of a subject matter? Elgin (2017) argues that this is not despite, but because, of models being literally false. She views false models as “felicitous falsehoods” that occupy center stage in the epistemology of science, and mentions the ideal-gas model in statistical mechanics and the Hardy–Weinberg model in genetics as examples for literally false models that are central to their respective disciplines. Understanding is holistic and it concerns a topic, a discipline, or a subject matter, rather than isolated claims or facts. Gaining understanding of a context means to have

an epistemic commitment to a comprehensive, systematically linked body of information that is grounded in fact, is duly responsive to reasons or evidence, and enables nontrivial inference, argument, and perhaps action regarding the topic the information pertains to (Elgin 2017: 44)

and models can play a crucial role in the pursuit of these epistemic commitments. For a discussion of Elgin’s account of models and understanding, see Baumberger and Brun (2017) and Frigg and Nguyen (forthcoming).

Elgin (2017), Lipton (2009), and Rice (2016) all argue that models can be used to understand independently of their ability to provide an explanation. Other authors, among them Strevens (2008, 2013), argue that understanding presupposes a scientific explanation and that

an individual has scientific understanding of a phenomenon just in case they grasp a correct scientific explanation of that phenomenon. (Strevens 2013: 510; see, however, Sullivan and Khalifa 2019)

On this account, understanding consists in a particular form of epistemic access an individual scientist has to an explanation. For Strevens this aspect is “grasping”, while for de Regt (2017) it is “intelligibility”. It is important to note that both Strevens and de Regt hold that such “subjective” aspects are a worthy topic for investigations in the philosophy of science. This contrasts with the traditional view (see, e.g., Hempel 1965) that delegates them to the realm of psychology. See Friedman (1974), Trout (2002), and Reutlinger et al. (2018) for further discussions of understanding.

Besides the functions already mentioned, it has been emphasized variously that models perform a number of other cognitive functions. Knuuttila (2005, 2011) argues that the epistemic value of models is not limited to their representational function, and develops an account that views models as epistemic artifacts which allow us to gather knowledge in diverse ways. Nersessian (1999, 2010) stresses the role of analogue models in concept-formation and other cognitive processes. Hartmann (1995) and Leplin (1980) discuss models as tools for theory construction and emphasize their heuristic and pedagogical value. Epstein (2008) lists a number of specific functions of models in the social sciences. Peschard (2011) investigates the way in which models may be used to construct other models and generate new target systems. And Isaac (2013) discusses non-explanatory uses of models which do not rely on their representational capacities.

4. Models and Theory

An important question concerns the relation between models and theories. There is a full spectrum of positions ranging from models being subordinate to theories to models being independent of theories.

To discuss the relation between models and theories in science it is helpful to briefly recapitulate the notions of a model and of a theory in logic. A theory is taken to be a (usually deductively closed) set of sentences in a formal language. A model is a structure (in the sense introduced in Section 2.3 ) that makes all sentences of a theory true when its symbols are interpreted as referring to objects, relations, or functions of a structure. The structure is a model of the theory in the sense that it is correctly described by the theory (see Bell and Machover 1977 or Hodges 1997 for details). Logical models are sometimes also referred to as “models of theory” to indicate that they are interpretations of an abstract formal system.

Models in science sometimes carry over from logic the idea of being the interpretation of an abstract calculus (Hesse 1967). This is salient in physics, where general laws—such as Newton’s equation of motion—lie at the heart of a theory. These laws are applied to a particular system—e.g., a pendulum—by choosing a special force function, making assumptions about the mass distribution of the pendulum etc. The resulting model then is an interpretation (or realization) of the general law.

It is important to keep the notions of a logical and a representational model separate (Thomson-Jones 2006): these are distinct concepts. Something can be a logical model without being a representational model, and vice versa . This, however, does not mean that something cannot be a model in both senses at once. In fact, as Hesse (1967) points out, many models in science are both logical and representational models. Newton’s model of planetary motion is a case in point: the model, consisting of two homogeneous perfect spheres located in otherwise empty space that attract each other gravitationally, is simultaneously a logical model (because it makes the axioms of Newtonian mechanics true when they are interpreted as referring to the model) and a representational model (because it represents the real sun and earth).

There are two main conceptions of scientific theories, the so-called syntactic view of theories and the so-called semantic view of theories (see the entry on the structure of scientific theories ). On both conceptions models play a subsidiary role to theories, albeit in very different ways. The syntactic view of theories (see entry section on the syntactic view ) retains the logical notions of a model and a theory. It construes a theory as a set of sentences in an axiomatized logical system, and a model as an alternative interpretation of a certain calculus (Braithwaite 1953; Campbell 1920 [1957]; Nagel 1961; Spector 1965). If, for instance, we take the mathematics used in the kinetic theory of gases and reinterpret the terms of this calculus in a way that makes them refer to billiard balls, the billiard balls are a model of the kinetic theory of gases in the sense that all sentences of the theory come out true. The model is meant to be something that we are familiar with, and it serves the purpose of making an abstract formal calculus more palpable. A given theory can have different models, and which model we choose depends both on our aims and our background knowledge. Proponents of the syntactic view disagree about the importance of models. Carnap and Hempel thought that models only serve a pedagogic or aesthetic purpose and are ultimately dispensable because all relevant information is contained in the theory (Carnap 1938; Hempel 1965; see also Bailer-Jones 1999). Nagel (1961) and Braithwaite (1953), on the other hand, emphasize the heuristic role of models, and Schaffner (1969) submits that theoretical terms get at least part of their meaning from models.

The semantic view of theories (see entry section on the semantic view ) dispenses with sentences in an axiomatized logical system and construes a theory as a family of models. On this view, a theory literally is a class, cluster, or family of models—models are the building blocks of which scientific theories are made up. Different versions of the semantic view work with different notions of a model, but, as noted in Section 2.3 , in the semantic view models are mostly construed as set-theoretic structures. For a discussion of the different options, we refer the reader to the relevant entry in this encyclopedia (linked at the beginning of this paragraph).

In both the syntactic and the semantic view of theories models are seen as subordinate to theory and as playing no role outside the context of a theory. This vision of models has been challenged in a number of ways, with authors pointing out that models enjoy various degrees of freedom from theory and function autonomously in many contexts. Independence can take many forms, and large parts of the literature on models are concerned with investigating various forms of independence.

Models as completely independent of theory . The most radical departure from a theory-centered analysis of models is the realization that there are models that are completely independent from any theory. An example of such a model is the Lotka–Volterra model. The model describes the interaction of two populations: a population of predators and one of prey animals (Weisberg 2013). The model was constructed using only relatively commonsensical assumptions about predators and prey and the mathematics of differential equations. There was no appeal to a theory of predator–prey interactions or a theory of population growth, and the model is independent of theories about its subject matter. If a model is constructed in a domain where no theory is available, then the model is sometimes referred to as a “substitute model” (Groenewold 1961), because the model substitutes a theory.

Models as a means to explore theory . Models can also be used to explore theories (Morgan and Morrison 1999). An obvious way in which this can happen is when a model is a logical model of a theory (see Section 4.1 ). A logical model is a set of objects and properties that make a formal sentence true, and so one can see in the model how the axioms of the theory play out in a particular setting and what kinds of behavior they dictate. But not all models that are used to explore theories are logical models, and models can represent features of theories in other ways. As an example, consider chaos theory. The equations of non-linear systems, such as those describing the three-body problem, have solutions that are too complex to study with paper-and-pencil methods, and even computer simulations are limited in various ways. Abstract considerations about the qualitative behavior of solutions show that there is a mechanism that has been dubbed “stretching and folding” (see the entry Chaos ). To obtain an idea of the complexity of the dynamics exhibiting stretching and folding, Smale proposed to study a simple model of the flow—now known as the “horseshoe map” (Tabor 1989)—which provides important insights into the nature of stretching and folding. Other examples of models of that kind are the Kac ring model that is used to study equilibrium properties of systems in statistical mechanics (Lavis 2008) and Norton’s dome in Newtonian mechanics (Norton 2003).

Models as complements of theories . A theory may be incompletely specified in the sense that it only imposes certain general constraints but remains silent about the details of concrete situations, which are provided by a model (Redhead 1980). A special case of this situation is when a qualitative theory is known and the model introduces quantitative measures (Apostel 1961). Redhead’s example of a theory that is underdetermined in this way is axiomatic quantum field theory, which only imposes certain general constraints on quantum fields but does not provide an account of particular fields. Harré (2004) notes that models can complement theories by providing mechanisms for processes that are left unspecified in the theory even though they are responsible for bringing about the observed phenomena.

Theories may be too complicated to handle. In such cases a model can complement a theory by providing a simplified version of the theoretical scenario that allows for a solution. Quantum chromodynamics, for instance, cannot easily be used to investigate the physics of an atomic nucleus even though it is the relevant fundamental theory. To get around this difficulty, physicists construct tractable phenomenological models (such as the MIT bag model) which effectively describe the relevant degrees of freedom of the system under consideration (Hartmann 1999, 2001). The advantage of these models is that they yield results where theories remain silent. Their drawback is that it is often not clear how to understand the relationship between the model and the theory, as the two are, strictly speaking, contradictory.

Models as preliminary theories . The notion of a model as a substitute for a theory is closely related to the notion of a developmental model . This term was coined by Leplin (1980), who pointed out how useful models were in the development of early quantum theory, and it is now used as an umbrella notion covering cases in which models are some sort of a preliminary exercise to theory.

Also closely related is the notion of a probing model (or “study model”). Models of this kind do not perform a representational function and are not expected to instruct us about anything beyond the model itself. The purpose of these models is to test new theoretical tools that are used later on to build representational models. In field theory, for instance, the so-called φ 4 -model was studied extensively, not because it was believed to represent anything real, but because it served several heuristic functions: the simplicity of the φ 4 -model allowed physicists to “get a feeling” for what quantum field theories are like and to extract some general features that this simple model shared with more complicated ones. Physicists could study complicated techniques such as renormalization in a simple setting, and it was possible to get acquainted with important mechanisms—in this case symmetry-breaking—that could later be used in different contexts (Hartmann 1995). This is true not only for physics. As Wimsatt (1987, 2007) points out, a false model in genetics can perform many useful functions, among them the following: the false model can help answering questions about more realistic models, provide an arena for answering questions about properties of more complex models, “factor out” phenomena that would not otherwise be seen, serve as a limiting case of a more general model (or two false models may define the extremes of a continuum of cases on which the real case is supposed to lie), or lead to the identification of relevant variables and the estimation of their values.

Interpretative models . Cartwright (1983, 1999) argues that models do not only aid the application of theories that are somehow incomplete; she claims that models are also involved whenever a theory with an overarching mathematical structure is applied. The main theories in physics—classical mechanics, electrodynamics, quantum mechanics, and so on—fall into this category. Theories of that kind are formulated in terms of abstract concepts that need to be concretized for the theory to provide a description of the target system, and concretizing the relevant concepts, idealized objects and processes are introduced. For instance, when applying classical mechanics, the abstract concept of force has to be replaced with a concrete force such as gravity. To obtain tractable equations, this procedure has to be applied to a simplified scenario, for instance that of two perfectly spherical and homogeneous planets in otherwise empty space, rather than to reality in its full complexity. The result is an interpretative model , which grounds the application of mathematical theories to real-world targets. Such models are independent from theory in that the theory does not determine their form, and yet they are necessary for the application of the theory to a concrete problem.

Models as mediators . The relation between models and theories can be complicated and disorderly. The contributors to a programmatic collection of essays edited by Morgan and Morrison (1999) rally around the idea that models are instruments that mediate between theories and the world. Models are “autonomous agents” in that they are independent from both theories and their target systems, and it is this independence that allows them to mediate between the two. Theories do not provide us with algorithms for the construction of a model; they are not “vending machines” into which one can insert a problem and a model pops out (Cartwright 1999). The construction of a model often requires detailed knowledge about materials, approximation schemes, and the setup, and these are not provided by the corresponding theory. Furthermore, the inner workings of a model are often driven by a number of different theories working cooperatively. In contemporary climate modeling, for instance, elements of different theories—among them fluid dynamics, thermodynamics, electromagnetism—are put to work cooperatively. What delivers the results is not the stringent application of one theory, but the voices of different theories when put to use in chorus with each other in one model.

In complex cases like the study of a laser system or the global climate, models and theories can get so entangled that it becomes unclear where a line between the two should be drawn: where does the model end and the theory begin? This is not only a problem for philosophical analysis; it also arises in scientific practice. Bailer-Jones (2002) interviewed a group of physicists about their understanding of models and their relation to theories, and reports widely diverging views: (i) there is no substantive difference between model and theory; (ii) models become theories when their degree of confirmation increases; (iii) models contain simplifications and omissions, while theories are accurate and complete; (iv) theories are more general than models, and modeling is about applying general theories to specific cases. The first suggestion seems to be too radical to do justice to many aspects of practice, where a distinction between models and theories is clearly made. The second view is in line with common parlance, where the terms “model” and “theory” are sometimes used to express someone’s attitude towards a particular hypothesis. The phrase “it’s just a model” indicates that the hypothesis at stake is asserted only tentatively or is even known to be false, while something is awarded the label “theory” if it has acquired some degree of general acceptance. However, this use of “model” is different from the uses we have seen in Sections 1 to 3 and is therefore of no use if we aim to understand the relation between scientific models and theories (and, incidentally, one can equally dismiss speculative claims as being “just a theory”). The third proposal is correct in associating models with idealizations and simplifications, but it overshoots by restricting this to models; in fact, also theories can contain idealizations and simplifications. The fourth view seems closely aligned with interpretative models and the idea that models are mediators, but being more general is a gradual notion and hence does not provide a clear-cut criterion to distinguish between theories and models.

5. Models and Other Debates in the Philosophy of Science

The debate over scientific models has important repercussions for other issues in the philosophy of science (for a historical account of the philosophical discussion about models, see Bailer-Jones 1999). Traditionally, the debates over, say, scientific realism, reductionism, and laws of nature were couched in terms of theories, because theories were seen as the main carriers of scientific knowledge. Once models are acknowledged as occupying an important place in the edifice of science, these issues have to be reconsidered with a focus on models. The question is whether, and if so how, discussions of these issues change when we shift focus from theories to models. Up to now, no comprehensive model-based account of any of these issues has emerged, but models have left important traces in the discussions of these topics.

As we have seen in Section 1 , models typically provide a distorted representation of their targets. If one sees science as primarily model-based, this could be taken to suggest an antirealist interpretation of science. Realists, however, deny that the presence of idealizations in models renders a realist approach to science impossible and point out that a good model, while not literally true, is usually at least approximately true, and/or that it can be improved by de-idealization (Laymon 1985; McMullin 1985; Nowak 1979; Brzezinski and Nowak 1992).

Apart from the usual worries about the elusiveness of the notion of approximate truth (for a discussion, see the entry on truthlikeness ), antirealists have taken issue with this reply for two (related) reasons. First, as Cartwright (1989) points out, there is no reason to assume that one can always improve a model by adding de-idealizing corrections. Second, it seems that de-idealization is not in accordance with scientific practice because it is unusual that scientists invest work in repeatedly de-idealizing an existing model. Rather, they shift to a different modeling framework once the adjustments to be made get too involved (Hartmann 1998). The various models of the atomic nucleus are a case in point: once it was realized that shell effects are important to understand various subatomic phenomena, the (collective) liquid-drop model was put aside and the (single-particle) shell model was developed to account for the corresponding findings. A further difficulty with de-idealization is that most idealizations are not “controlled”. For example, it is not clear in what way one could de-idealize the MIT bag model to eventually arrive at quantum chromodynamics, the supposedly correct underlying theory.

A further antirealist argument, the “incompatible-models argument”, takes as its starting point the observation that scientists often successfully use several incompatible models of one and the same target system for predictive purposes (Morrison 2000). These models seemingly contradict each other, as they ascribe different properties to the same target system. In nuclear physics, for instance, the liquid-drop model explores the analogy of the atomic nucleus with a (charged) fluid drop, while the shell model describes nuclear properties in terms of the properties of protons and neutrons, the constituents of an atomic nucleus. This practice appears to cause a problem for scientific realism: Realists typically hold that there is a close connection between the predictive success of a theory and its being at least approximately true. But if several models of the same system are predictively successful and if these models are mutually inconsistent, then it is difficult to maintain that they are all approximately true.

Realists can react to this argument in various ways. First, they can challenge the claim that the models in question are indeed predictively successful. If the models are not good predictors, then the argument is blocked. Second, they can defend a version of “perspectival realism” (Giere 2006; Massimi 2017; Rueger 2005). Proponents of this position (which is sometimes also called “perspectivism”) situate it somewhere between “standard” scientific realism and antirealism, and where exactly the right middle position lies is the subject matter of active debate (Massimi 2018a,b; Saatsi 2016; Teller 2018; and the contributions to Massimi and McCoy 2019). Third, realists can deny that there is a problem in the first place, because scientific models, which are always idealized and therefore strictly speaking false, are just the wrong vehicle to make a point about realism (which should be discussed in terms of theories).

A particular focal point of the realism debate are laws of nature, where the questions arise what laws are and whether they are truthfully reflected in our scientific representations. According to the two currently dominant accounts, the best-systems approach and the necessitarian approach, laws of nature are understood to be universal in scope, meaning that they apply to everything that there is in the world (for discussion of laws, see the entry on laws of nature ). This take on laws does not seem to sit well with a view that places models at the center of scientific research. What role do general laws play in science if it is models that represent what is happening in the world? And how are models and laws related?

One possible response to these questions is to argue that laws of nature govern entities and processes in a model rather than in the world. Fundamental laws, on this approach, do not state facts about the world but hold true of entities and processes in the model. This view has been advocated in different variants: Cartwright (1983) argues that all laws are ceteris paribus laws. Cartwright (1999) makes use of “capacities” (which she considers to be prior to laws) and introduces the notion of a “nomological machine”. This is

a fixed (enough) arrangement of components, or factors, with stable (enough) capacities that in the right sort of stable (enough) environment will, with repeated operation, give rise to the kind of regular behavior that we represent in our scientific laws. (1999: 50; see also the entry on ceteris paribus laws )

Giere (1999) argues that the laws of a theory are better thought of, not as encoding general truths about the world, but rather as open-ended statements that can be filled in various ways in the process of building more specific scientific models. Similar positions have also been defended by Teller (2001) and van Fraassen (1989).

The multiple-models problem mentioned in Section 5.1 also raises the question of how different models are related. Evidently, multiple models for the same target system do not generally stand in a deductive relationship, as they often contradict each other. Some (Cartwright 1999; Hacking 1983) have suggested a picture of science according to which there are no systematic relations that hold between different models. Some models are tied together because they represent the same target system, but this does not imply that they enter into any further relationships (deductive or otherwise). We are confronted with a patchwork of models, all of which hold ceteris paribus in their specific domains of applicability.

Some argue that this picture is at least partially incorrect because there are various interesting relations that hold between different models or theories. These relations range from thoroughgoing reductive relations (Scheibe 1997, 1999, 2001: esp. Chs. V.23 and V.24) and controlled approximations over singular limit relations (Batterman 2001 [2016]) to structural relations (Gähde 1997) and rather loose relations called “stories” (Hartmann 1999; see also Bokulich 2003; Teller 2002; and the essays collected in Part III of Hartmann et al. 2008). These suggestions have been made on the basis of case studies, and it remains to be seen whether a more general account of these relations can be given and whether a deeper justification for them can be provided, for instance, within a Bayesian framework (first steps towards a Bayesian understanding of reductive relations can be found in Dizadji-Bahmani et al. 2011; Liefke and Hartmann 2018; and Tešić 2019).

Models also figure in the debate about reduction and emergence in physics. Here, some authors argue that the modern approach to renormalization challenges Nagel’s (1961) model of reduction or the broader doctrine of reductions (for a critical discussion, see, for instance, Batterman 2002, 2010, 2011; Morrison 2012; and Saatsi and Reutlinger 2018). Dizadji-Bahmani et al. (2010) provide a defense of the Nagel–Schaffner model of reduction, and Butterfield (2011a,b, 2014) argues that renormalization is consistent with Nagelian reduction. Palacios (2019) shows that phase transitions are compatible with reductionism, and Hartmann (2001) argues that the effective-field-theories research program is consistent with reductionism (see also Bain 2013 and Franklin forthcoming). Rosaler (2015) argues for a “local” form of reduction which sees the fundamental relation of reduction holding between models, not theories, which is, however, compatible with the Nagel–Schaffner model of reduction. See also the entries on intertheory relations in physics and scientific reduction .

In the social sciences, agent-based models (ABMs) are increasingly used (Klein et al. 2018). These models show how surprisingly complex behavioral patterns at the macro-scale can emerge from a small number of simple behavioral rules for the individual agents and their interactions. This raises questions similar to the questions mentioned above about reduction and emergence in physics, but so far one only finds scattered remarks about reduction in the literature. See Weisberg and Muldoon (2009) and Zollman (2007) for the application of ABMs to the epistemology and the social structure of science, and Colyvan (2013) for a discussion of methodological questions raised by normative models in general.

  • Achinstein, Peter, 1968, Concepts of Science: A Philosophical Analysis , Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Press.
  • Akerlof, George A., 1970, “The Market for ‘Lemons’: Quality Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism”, The Quarterly Journal of Economics , 84(3): 488–500. doi:10.2307/1879431
  • Apostel, Leo, 1961, “Towards the Formal Study of Models in the Non-Formal Sciences”, in Freudenthal 1961: 1–37. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-3667-2_1
  • Bailer-Jones, Daniela M., 1999, “Tracing the Development of Models in the Philosophy of Science”, in Magnani, Nersessian, and Thagard 1999: 23–40. doi:10.1007/978-1-4615-4813-3_2
  • –––, 2002, “Scientists’ Thoughts on Scientific Models”, Perspectives on Science , 10(3): 275–301. doi:10.1162/106361402321899069
  • –––, 2009, Scientific Models in Philosophy of Science , Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.
  • Bailer-Jones, Daniela M. and Coryn A. L. Bailer-Jones, 2002, “Modeling Data: Analogies in Neural Networks, Simulated Annealing and Genetic Algorithms”, in Magnani and Nersessian 2002: 147–165. doi:10.1007/978-1-4615-0605-8_9
  • Bain, Jonathan, 2013, “Emergence in Effective Field Theories”, European Journal for Philosophy of Science , 3(3): 257–273. doi:10.1007/s13194-013-0067-0
  • Bandyopadhyay, Prasanta S. and Malcolm R. Forster (eds.), 2011, Philosophy of Statistics (Handbook of the Philosophy of Science 7), Amsterdam: Elsevier.
  • Barberousse, Anouk and Pascal Ludwig, 2009, “Fictions and Models”, in Suárez 2009: 56–75.
  • Bartha, Paul, 2010, By Parallel Reasoning: The Construction and Evaluation of Analogical Arguments , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195325539.001.0001
  • –––, 2013 [2019], “Analogy and Analogical Reasoning”, in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition). URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/reasoning-analogy/ >
  • Batterman, Robert W., 2002, The Devil in the Details: Asymptotic Reasoning in Explanation, Reduction, and Emergence , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0195146476.001.0001
  • –––, 2001 [2016], “Intertheory Relations in Physics”, in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2016 Edition). URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/physics-interrelate >
  • –––, 2010, “Reduction and Renormalization”, in Gerhard Ernst and Andreas Hüttemann (eds.), Time, Chance and Reduction: Philosophical Aspects of Statistical Mechanics , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 159–179.
  • –––, 2011, “Emergence, Singularities, and Symmetry Breaking”, Foundations of Physics , 41(6): 1031–1050. doi:10.1007/s10701-010-9493-4
  • Batterman, Robert W. and Collin C. Rice, 2014, “Minimal Model Explanations”, Philosophy of Science , 81(3): 349–376. doi:10.1086/676677
  • Baumberger, Christoph and Georg Brun, 2017, “Dimensions of Objectual Understanding”, in Stephen R. Grimm, Christoph Baumberger, and Sabine Ammon (eds.), Explaining Understanding: New Perspectives from Epistemology and Philosophy of Science , New York: Routledge, pp. 165–189.
  • Bell, John and Moshé Machover, 1977, A Course in Mathematical Logic , Amsterdam: North-Holland.
  • Berry, Michael, 2002, “Singular Limits”, Physics Today , 55(5): 10–11. doi:10.1063/1.1485555
  • Black, Max, 1962, Models and Metaphors: Studies in Language and Philosophy , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • Bogen, James and James Woodward, 1988, “Saving the Phenomena”, The Philosophical Review , 97(3): 303–352. doi:10.2307/2185445
  • Bokulich, Alisa, 2003, “Horizontal Models: From Bakers to Cats”, Philosophy of Science , 70(3): 609–627. doi:10.1086/376927
  • –––, 2008, Reexamining the Quantum–Classical Relation: Beyond Reductionism and Pluralism , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511751813
  • –––, 2009, “Explanatory Fictions”, in Suárez 2009: 91–109.
  • –––, 2011, “How Scientific Models Can Explain”, Synthese , 180(1): 33–45. doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9565-1
  • –––, 2012, “Distinguishing Explanatory from Nonexplanatory Fictions”, Philosophy of Science , 79(5): 725–737. doi:10.1086/667991
  • Braithwaite, Richard, 1953, Scientific Explanation , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Braun, Norman and Nicole J. Saam (eds.), 2015, Handbuch Modellbildung und Simulation in den Sozialwissenschaften , Wiesbaden: Springer Fachmedien. doi:10.1007/978-3-658-01164-2
  • Brewer, William F. and Clark A. Chinn, 1994, “Scientists’ Responses to Anomalous Data: Evidence from Psychology, History, and Philosophy of Science”, in PSA 1994: Proceedings of the 1994 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association , Vol. 1, pp. 304–313. doi:10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1994.1.193035
  • Brown, James, 1991, The Laboratory of the Mind: Thought Experiments in the Natural Sciences , London: Routledge.
  • Brzezinski, Jerzy and Leszek Nowak (eds.), 1992, Idealization III: Approximation and Truth , Amsterdam: Rodopi.
  • Butterfield, Jeremy, 2011a, “Emergence, Reduction and Supervenience: A Varied Landscape”, Foundations of Physics , 41(6): 920–959. doi:10.1007/s10701-011-9549-0
  • –––, 2011b, “Less Is Different: Emergence and Reduction Reconciled”, Foundations of Physics , 41(6): 1065–1135. doi:10.1007/s10701-010-9516-1
  • –––, 2014, “Reduction, Emergence, and Renormalization”, Journal of Philosophy , 111(1): 5–49. doi:10.5840/jphil201411111
  • Callender, Craig and Jonathan Cohen, 2006, “There Is No Special Problem about Scientific Representation”, Theoria , 55(1): 67–85.
  • Campbell, Norman, 1920 [1957], Physics: The Elements , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reprinted as Foundations of Science , New York: Dover, 1957.
  • Carnap, Rudolf, 1938, “Foundations of Logic and Mathematics”, in Otto Neurath, Charles Morris, and Rudolf Carnap (eds.), International Encyclopaedia of Unified Science , Volume 1, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, pp. 139–213.
  • Cartwright, Nancy, 1983, How the Laws of Physics Lie , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0198247044.001.0001
  • –––, 1989, Nature’s Capacities and Their Measurement , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0198235070.001.0001
  • –––, 1999, The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139167093
  • Colombo, Matteo, Stephan Hartmann, and Robert van Iersel, 2015, “Models, Mechanisms, and Coherence”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 66(1): 181–212. doi:10.1093/bjps/axt043
  • Colyvan, Mark, 2013, “Idealisations in Normative Models”, Synthese , 190(8): 1337–1350. doi:10.1007/s11229-012-0166-z
  • Contessa, Gabriele, 2010, “Scientific Models and Fictional Objects”, Synthese , 172(2): 215–229. doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9503-2
  • Crowther, Karen, Niels S. Linnemann, and Christian Wüthrich, forthcoming, “What We Cannot Learn from Analogue Experiments”, Synthese , first online: 4 May 2019. doi:10.1007/s11229-019-02190-0
  • Da Costa, Newton and Steven French, 2000, “Models, Theories, and Structures: Thirty Years On”, Philosophy of Science , 67(supplement): S116–S127. doi:10.1086/392813
  • Dardashti, Radin, Stephan Hartmann, Karim Thébault, and Eric Winsberg, 2019, “Hawking Radiation and Analogue Experiments: A Bayesian Analysis”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics , 67: 1–11. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2019.04.004
  • Dardashti, Radin, Karim P. Y. Thébault, and Eric Winsberg, 2017, “Confirmation via Analogue Simulation: What Dumb Holes Could Tell Us about Gravity”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 68(1): 55–89. doi:10.1093/bjps/axv010
  • de Regt, Henk, 2009, “Understanding and Scientific Explanation”, in de Regt, Leonelli, and Eigner 2009: 21–42.
  • –––, 2017, Understanding Scientific Understanding , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780190652913.001.0001
  • de Regt, Henk, Sabina Leonelli, and Kai Eigner (eds.), 2009, Scientific Understanding: Philosophical Perspectives , Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.
  • Dizadji-Bahmani, Foad, Roman Frigg, and Stephan Hartmann, 2010, “Who’s Afraid of Nagelian Reduction?”, Erkenntnis , 73(3): 393–412. doi:10.1007/s10670-010-9239-x
  • –––, 2011, “Confirmation and Reduction: A Bayesian Account”, Synthese , 179(2): 321–338. doi:10.1007/s11229-010-9775-6
  • Downes, Stephen M., 1992, “The Importance of Models in Theorizing: A Deflationary Semantic View”, PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association , 1992(1): 142–153. doi:10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1992.1.192750
  • Elgin, Catherine Z., 2010, “Telling Instances”, in Roman Frigg and Matthew Hunter (eds.), Beyond Mimesis and Convention (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 262), Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, pp. 1–17. doi:10.1007/978-90-481-3851-7_1
  • –––, 2017, True Enough . Cambridge, MA, and London: MIT Press.
  • Elgin, Mehmet and Elliott Sober, 2002, “Cartwright on Explanation and Idealization”, Erkenntnis , 57(3): 441–450. doi:10.1023/A:1021502932490
  • Epstein, Joshua M., 2008, “Why Model?”, Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation , 11(4): 12. [ Epstein 2008 available online ]
  • Fisher, Grant, 2006, “The Autonomy of Models and Explanation: Anomalous Molecular Rearrangements in Early Twentieth-Century Physical Organic Chemistry”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A , 37(4): 562–584. doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2006.09.009
  • Franklin, Alexander, forthcoming, “Whence the Effectiveness of Effective Field Theories?”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , first online: 3 August 2018. doi:10.1093/bjps/axy050
  • Freudenthal, Hans (ed.), 1961, The Concept and the Role of the Model in Mathematics and Natural and Social Sciences , Dordrecht: Reidel. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-3667-2
  • Friedman, Michael, 1974, “Explanation and Scientific Understanding”, Journal of Philosophy , 71(1): 5–19. doi:10.2307/2024924
  • Frigg, Roman, 2010a, “Fiction in Science”, in John Woods (ed.), Fictions and Models: New Essays , Munich: Philosophia Verlag, pp. 247–287.
  • –––, 2010b, “Models and Fiction”, Synthese , 172(2): 251–268. doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9505-0
  • Frigg, Roman, Seamus Bradley, Hailiang Du, and Leonard A. Smith, 2014, “Laplace’s Demon and the Adventures of His Apprentices”, Philosophy of Science , 81(1): 31–59. doi:10.1086/674416
  • Frigg, Roman and James Nguyen, 2016, “The Fiction View of Models Reloaded”, The Monist , 99(3): 225–242. doi:10.1093/monist/onw002 [ Frigg and Nguyen 2016 available online ]
  • –––, forthcoming, “Mirrors without Warnings”, Synthese , first online: 21 May 2019. doi:10.1007/s11229-019-02222-9
  • Fumagalli, Roberto, 2016, “Why We Cannot Learn from Minimal Models”, Erkenntnis , 81(3): 433–455. doi:10.1007/s10670-015-9749-7
  • Gähde, Ulrich, 1997, “Anomalies and the Revision of Theory-Elements: Notes on the Advance of Mercury’s Perihelion”, in Maria Luisa Dalla Chiara, Kees Doets, Daniele Mundici, and Johan van Benthem (eds.), Structures and Norms in Science (Synthese Library 260), Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, pp. 89–104. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-0538-7_6
  • Galison, Peter, 1997, Image and Logic: A Material Culture of Microphysics , Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • Gelfert, Axel, 2016, How to Do Science with Models: A Philosophical Primer (Springer Briefs in Philosophy), Cham: Springer International Publishing. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-27954-1
  • Gendler, Tamar Szabó, 2000, Thought Experiment: On the Powers and Limits of Imaginary Cases , New York and London: Garland.
  • Gibbard, Allan and Hal R. Varian, 1978, “Economic Models”, The Journal of Philosophy , 75(11): 664–677. doi:10.5840/jphil1978751111
  • Giere, Ronald N., 1988, Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach , Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • –––, 1999, Science Without Laws , Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • –––, 2006, Scientific Perspectivism , Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • –––, 2009, “Why Scientific Models Should Not be Regarded as Works of Fiction”, in Suárez 2009: 248–258.
  • –––, 2010, “An Agent-Based Conception of Models and Scientific Representation”, Synthese , 172(2): 269–281. doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9506-z
  • Godfrey-Smith, Peter, 2007, “The Strategy of Model-Based Science”, Biology & Philosophy , 21(5): 725–740. doi:10.1007/s10539-006-9054-6
  • –––, 2009, “Abstractions, Idealizations, and Evolutionary Biology”, in Anouk Barberousse, Michel Morange, and Thomas Pradeu (eds.), Mapping the Future of Biology: Evolving Concepts and Theories (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 266), Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, pp. 47–56. doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-9636-5_4
  • Groenewold, H. J., 1961, “The Model in Physics”, in Freudenthal 1961: 98–103. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-3667-2_9
  • Grüne-Yanoff, Till, 2009, “Learning from Minimal Economic Models”, Erkenntnis , 70(1): 81–99. doi:10.1007/s10670-008-9138-6
  • Hacking, Ian, 1983, Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511814563
  • Hale, Susan C., 1988, “Spacetime and the Abstract/Concrete Distinction”, Philosophical Studies , 53(1): 85–102. doi:10.1007/BF00355677
  • Harré, Rom, 2004, Modeling: Gateway to the Unknown (Studies in Multidisciplinarity 1), ed. by Daniel Rothbart, Amsterdam etc.: Elsevier.
  • Harris, Todd, 2003, “Data Models and the Acquisition and Manipulation of Data”, Philosophy of Science , 70(5): 1508–1517. doi:10.1086/377426
  • Hartmann, Stephan, 1995, “Models as a Tool for Theory Construction: Some Strategies of Preliminary Physics”, in Herfel et al. 1995: 49–67.
  • –––, 1996, “The World as a Process: Simulations in the Natural and Social Sciences”, in Hegselmann, Mueller, and Troitzsch 1996: 77–100. doi:10.1007/978-94-015-8686-3_5
  • –––, 1998, “Idealization in Quantum Field Theory”, in Shanks 1998: 99–122.
  • –––, 1999, “Models and Stories in Hadron Physics”, in Morgan and Morrison 1999: 326–346. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511660108.012
  • –––, 2001, “Effective Field Theories, Reductionism and Scientific Explanation”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics , 32(2): 267–304. doi:10.1016/S1355-2198(01)00005-3
  • Hartmann, Stephan, Carl Hoefer, and Luc Bovens (eds.), 2008, Nancy Cartwright’s Philosophy of Science (Routledge Studies in the Philosophy of Science), New York: Routledge.
  • Hegselmann, Rainer, Ulrich Mueller, and Klaus G. Troitzsch (eds.), 1996, Modelling and Simulation in the Social Sciences from the Philosophy of Science Point of View (Theory and Decision Library 23), Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. doi:10.1007/978-94-015-8686-3
  • Helman, David H. (ed.), 1988, Analogical Reasoning: Perspectives of Artificial Intelligence, Cognitive Science, and Philosophy (Synthese Library 197), Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. doi:10.1007/978-94-015-7811-0
  • Hempel, Carl G., 1965, Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science , New York: Free Press.
  • Herfel, William, Wladiysław Krajewski, Ilkka Niiniluoto, and Ryszard Wojcicki (eds.), 1995, Theories and Models in Scientific Process (Poznań Studies in the Philosophy of Science and the Humanities 44), Amsterdam: Rodopi.
  • Hesse, Mary, 1963, Models and Analogies in Science , London: Sheed and Ward.
  • –––, 1967, “Models and Analogy in Science”, in Paul Edwards (ed.), Encyclopedia of Philosophy , New York: Macmillan, pp. 354–359.
  • –––, 1974, The Structure of Scientific Inference , London: Macmillan.
  • Hodges, Wilfrid, 1997, A Shorter Model Theory , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Holyoak, Keith and Paul Thagard, 1995, Mental Leaps: Analogy in Creative Thought , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Horowitz, Tamara and Gerald J. Massey (eds.), 1991, Thought Experiments in Science and Philosophy , Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Isaac, Alistair M. C., 2013, “Modeling without Representation”, Synthese , 190(16): 3611–3623. doi:10.1007/s11229-012-0213-9
  • Jebeile, Julie and Ashley Graham Kennedy, 2015, “Explaining with Models: The Role of Idealizations”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science , 29(4): 383–392. doi:10.1080/02698595.2015.1195143
  • Jones, Martin R., 2005, “Idealization and Abstraction: A Framework”, in Jones and Cartwright 2005: 173–217. doi:10.1163/9789401202732_010
  • Jones, Martin R. and Nancy Cartwright (eds.), 2005, Idealization XII: Correcting the Model (Poznań Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 86), Amsterdam and New York: Rodopi. doi:10.1163/9789401202732
  • Kelvin, William Thomson, Baron, 1884 [1987], Notes of lectures on molecular dynamics and the wave theory of light. Delivered at the Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore (aka Lord Kelvin’s Baltimore Lectures), A. S. Hathaway (recorder). A revised version was published in 1904, London: C.J. Clay and Sons. Reprint of the 1884 version in Robert Kargon and Peter Achinstein (eds.), Kelvin’s Baltimore Lectures and Modern Theoretical Physics , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987.
  • Khalifa, Kareem, 2017, Understanding, Explanation, and Scientific Knowledge , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/9781108164276
  • Klein, Dominik, Johannes Marx, and Kai Fischbach, 2018, “Agent-Based Modeling in Social Science History and Philosophy: An Introduction”, Historical Social Research , 43(1): 243–258.
  • Knuuttila, Tarja, 2005, “Models, Representation, and Mediation”, Philosophy of Science , 72(5): 1260–1271. doi:10.1086/508124
  • –––, 2011, “Modelling and Representing: An Artefactual Approach to Model-Based Representation”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A , 42(2): 262–271. doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2010.11.034
  • Kroes, Peter, 1989, “Structural Analogies Between Physical Systems”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 40(2): 145–154. doi:10.1093/bjps/40.2.145
  • Lange, Marc, 2015, “On ‘Minimal Model Explanations’: A Reply to Batterman and Rice”, Philosophy of Science , 82(2): 292–305. doi:10.1086/680488
  • Lavis, David A., 2008, “Boltzmann, Gibbs, and the Concept of Equilibrium”, Philosophy of Science , 75(5): 682–692. doi:10.1086/594514
  • Laymon, Ronald, 1982, “Scientific Realism and the Hierarchical Counterfactual Path from Data to Theory”, PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association , 1982(1): 107–121. doi:10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1982.1.192660
  • –––, 1985, “Idealizations and the Testing of Theories by Experimentation”, in Peter Achinstein and Owen Hannaway (eds.), Observation, Experiment, and Hypothesis in Modern Physical Science , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 147–173.
  • –––, 1991, “Thought Experiments by Stevin, Mach and Gouy: Thought Experiments as Ideal Limits and Semantic Domains”, in Horowitz and Massey 1991: 167–191.
  • Leonelli, Sabina, 2010, “Packaging Small Facts for Re-Use: Databases in Model Organism Biology”, in Peter Howlett and Mary S. Morgan (eds.), How Well Do Facts Travel? The Dissemination of Reliable Knowledge , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 325–348. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511762154.017
  • –––, 2016, Data-Centric Biology: A Philosophical Study , Chicago, IL, and London: University of Chicago Press.
  • –––, 2019, “What Distinguishes Data from Models?”, European Journal for Philosophy of Science , 9(2): article 22. doi:10.1007/s13194-018-0246-0
  • Leonelli, Sabina and Rachel A. Ankeny, 2012, “Re-Thinking Organisms: The Impact of Databases on Model Organism Biology”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences , 43(1): 29–36. doi:10.1016/j.shpsc.2011.10.003
  • Leplin, Jarrett, 1980, “The Role of Models in Theory Construction”, in Thomas Nickles (ed.), Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 56), Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 267–283. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-8986-3_12
  • Levy, Arnon, 2012, “Models, Fictions, and Realism: Two Packages”, Philosophy of Science , 79(5): 738–748. doi:10.1086/667992
  • –––, 2015, “Modeling without Models”, Philosophical Studies , 172(3): 781–798. doi:10.1007/s11098-014-0333-9
  • Levy, Arnon and Adrian Currie, 2015, “Model Organisms Are Not (Theoretical) Models”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 66(2): 327–348. doi:10.1093/bjps/axt055
  • Levy, Arnon and Peter Godfrey-Smith (eds.), 2020, The Scientific Imagination: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Liefke, Kristina and Stephan Hartmann, 2018, “Intertheoretic Reduction, Confirmation, and Montague’s Syntax–Semantics Relation”, Journal of Logic, Language and Information , 27(4): 313–341. doi:10.1007/s10849-018-9272-8
  • Lipton, Peter, 2009, “Understanding without Explanation”, in de Regt, Leonelli, and Eigner 2009: 43–63.
  • Luczak, Joshua, 2017, “Talk about Toy Models”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics , 57: 1–7. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2016.11.002
  • Magnani, Lorenzo, 2012, “Scientific Models Are Not Fictions: Model-Based Science as Epistemic Warfare”, in Lorenzo Magnani and Ping Li (eds.), Philosophy and Cognitive Science: Western & Eastern Studies (Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics 2), Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer, pp. 1–38. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-29928-5_1
  • Magnani, Lorenzo and Claudia Casadio (eds.), 2016, Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology: Logical, Epistemological, and Cognitive Issues (Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics 27), Cham: Springer International Publishing. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-38983-7
  • Magnani, Lorenzo and Nancy J. Nersessian (eds.), 2002, Model-Based Reasoning: Science, Technology, Values , Boston, MA: Springer US. doi:10.1007/978-1-4615-0605-8
  • Magnani, Lorenzo, Nancy J. Nersessian, and Paul Thagard (eds.), 1999, Model-Based Reasoning in Scientific Discovery , Boston, MA: Springer US. doi:10.1007/978-1-4615-4813-3
  • Mäki, Uskali, 1994, “Isolation, Idealization and Truth in Economics”, in Bert Hamminga and Neil B. De Marchi (eds.), Idealization VI: Idealization in Economics (Poznań Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 38), Amsterdam: Rodopi, pp. 147–168.
  • Massimi, Michela, 2017, “Perspectivism”, in Juha Saatsi (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Scientific Realism , London: Routledge, pp. 164–175.
  • –––, 2018a, “Four Kinds of Perspectival Truth”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , 96(2): 342–359. doi:10.1111/phpr.12300
  • –––, 2018b, “Perspectival Modeling”, Philosophy of Science , 85(3): 335–359. doi:10.1086/697745
  • –––, 2019, “Two Kinds of Exploratory Models”, Philosophy of Science , 86(5): 869–881. doi:10.1086/705494
  • Massimi, Michela and Casey D. McCoy (eds.), 2019, Understanding Perspectivism: Scientific Challenges and Methodological Prospects , New York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9781315145198
  • Mayo, Deborah, 1996, Error and the Growth of Experimental Knowledge , Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • –––, 2018, Statistical Inference as Severe Testing: How to Get Beyond the Statistics Wars , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/9781107286184
  • McMullin, Ernan, 1968, “What Do Physical Models Tell Us?”, in B. Van Rootselaar and J. Frits Staal (eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science III (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics 52), Amsterdam: North Holland, pp. 385–396. doi:10.1016/S0049-237X(08)71206-0
  • –––, 1985, “Galilean Idealization”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A , 16(3): 247–273. doi:10.1016/0039-3681(85)90003-2
  • Morgan, Mary S., 1999, “Learning from Models”, in Morgan and Morrison 1999: 347–388. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511660108.013
  • Morgan, Mary S. and Marcel J. Boumans, 2004, “Secrets Hidden by Two-Dimensionality: The Economy as a Hydraulic Machine”, in Soraya de Chadarevian and Nick Hopwood (eds.), Model: The Third Dimension of Science , Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, pp. 369–401.
  • Morgan, Mary S. and Margaret Morrison (eds.), 1999, Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511660108
  • Morrison, Margaret, 1999, “Models as Autonomous Agents”, in Morgan and Morrison 1999: 38–65. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511660108.004
  • –––, 2000, Unifying Scientific Theories: Physical Concepts and Mathematical Structures , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511527333
  • –––, 2005, “Approximating the Real: The Role of Idealizations in Physical Theory”, in Jones and Cartwright 2005: 145–172. doi:10.1163/9789401202732_009
  • –––, 2009, “Understanding in Physics and Biology: From the Abstract to the Concrete”, in de Regt, Leonelli, and Eigner 2009: 123–145.
  • –––, 2012, “Emergent Physics and Micro-Ontology”, Philosophy of Science , 79(1): 141–166. doi:10.1086/663240
  • Musgrave, Alan, 1981, “‘Unreal Assumptions’ in Economic Theory: The F-Twist Untwisted”, Kyklos , 34(3): 377–387. doi:10.1111/j.1467-6435.1981.tb01195.x
  • Nagel, Ernest, 1961, The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation , New York: Harcourt, Brace and World.
  • Nersessian, Nancy J., 1999, “Model-Based Reasoning in Conceptual Change”, in Magnani, Nersessian, and Thagard 1999: 5–22. doi:10.1007/978-1-4615-4813-3_1
  • –––, 2010, Creating Scientific Concepts , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Nguyen, James, forthcoming, “It’s Not a Game: Accurate Representation with Toy Models”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , first online: 23 March 2019. doi:10.1093/bjps/axz010
  • Nguyen, James and Roman Frigg, forthcoming, “Mathematics Is Not the Only Language in the Book of Nature”, Synthese , first online: 28 August 2017. doi:10.1007/s11229-017-1526-5
  • Norton, John D., 1991, “Thought Experiments in Einstein’s Work”, in Horowitz and Massey 1991: 129–148.
  • –––, 2003, “Causation as Folk Science”, Philosopher’s Imprint , 3: article 4. [ Norton 2003 available online ]
  • –––, 2012, “Approximation and Idealization: Why the Difference Matters”, Philosophy of Science , 79(2): 207–232. doi:10.1086/664746
  • Nowak, Leszek, 1979, The Structure of Idealization: Towards a Systematic Interpretation of the Marxian Idea of Science , Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
  • Palacios, Patricia, 2019, “Phase Transitions: A Challenge for Intertheoretic Reduction?”, Philosophy of Science , 86(4): 612–640. doi:10.1086/704974
  • Peschard, Isabelle, 2011, “Making Sense of Modeling: Beyond Representation”, European Journal for Philosophy of Science , 1(3): 335–352. doi:10.1007/s13194-011-0032-8
  • Piccinini, Gualtiero and Carl Craver, 2011, “Integrating Psychology and Neuroscience: Functional Analyses as Mechanism Sketches”, Synthese , 183(3): 283–311. doi:10.1007/s11229-011-9898-4
  • Pincock, Christopher, 2012, Mathematics and Scientific Representation , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199757107.001.0001
  • –––, forthcoming, “Concrete Scale Models, Essential Idealization and Causal Explanation”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science .
  • Portides, Demetris P., 2007, “The Relation between Idealisation and Approximation in Scientific Model Construction”, Science & Education , 16(7–8): 699–724. doi:10.1007/s11191-006-9001-6
  • –––, 2014, “How Scientific Models Differ from Works of Fiction”, in Lorenzo Magnani (ed.), Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology (Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics 8), Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer, pp. 75–87. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-37428-9_5
  • Potochnik, Angela, 2007, “Optimality Modeling and Explanatory Generality”, Philosophy of Science , 74(5): 680–691.
  • –––, 2017, Idealization and the Aims of Science , Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • Poznic, Michael, 2016, “Make-Believe and Model-Based Representation in Science: The Epistemology of Frigg’s and Toon’s Fictionalist Views of Modeling”, Teorema: Revista Internacional de Filosofía , 35(3): 201–218.
  • Psillos, Stathis, 1995, “The Cognitive Interplay between Theories and Models: The Case of 19th Century Optics”, in Herfel et al. 1995: 105–133.
  • Redhead, Michael, 1980, “Models in Physics”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 31(2): 145–163. doi:10.1093/bjps/31.2.145
  • Reiss, Julian, 2003, “Causal Inference in the Abstract or Seven Myths about Thought Experiments”, in Causality: Metaphysics and Methods Research Project , Technical Report 03/02. London: London School of Economics.
  • –––, 2006, “Social Capacities”, in Hartmann et al. 2006: 265–288.
  • –––, 2012, “The Explanation Paradox”, Journal of Economic Methodology , 19(1): 43–62. doi:10.1080/1350178X.2012.661069
  • Reutlinger, Alexander, 2017, “Do Renormalization Group Explanations Conform to the Commonality Strategy?”, Journal for General Philosophy of Science , 48(1): 143–150. doi:10.1007/s10838-016-9339-7
  • Reutlinger, Alexander, Dominik Hangleiter, and Stephan Hartmann, 2018, “Understanding (with) Toy Models”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 69(4): 1069–1099. doi:10.1093/bjps/axx005
  • Rice, Collin C., 2015, “Moving Beyond Causes: Optimality Models and Scientific Explanation”, Noûs , 49(3): 589–615. doi:10.1111/nous.12042
  • –––, 2016, “Factive Scientific Understanding without Accurate Representation”, Biology & Philosophy , 31(1): 81–102. doi:10.1007/s10539-015-9510-2
  • –––, 2018, “Idealized Models, Holistic Distortions, and Universality”, Synthese , 195(6): 2795–2819. doi:10.1007/s11229-017-1357-4
  • –––, 2019, “Models Don’t Decompose That Way: A Holistic View of Idealized Models”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 70(1): 179–208. doi:10.1093/bjps/axx045
  • Rosaler, Joshua, 2015, “Local Reduction in Physics”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics , 50: 54–69. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.02.004
  • Rueger, Alexander, 2005, “Perspectival Models and Theory Unification”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 56(3): 579–594. doi:10.1093/bjps/axi128
  • Rueger, Alexander and David Sharp, 1998, “Idealization and Stability: A Perspective from Nonlinear Dynamics”, in Shanks 1998: 201–216.
  • Saatsi, Juha, 2016, “Models, Idealisations, and Realism”, in Emiliano Ippoliti, Fabio Sterpetti, and Thomas Nickles (eds.), Models and Inferences in Science (Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics 25), Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 173–189. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-28163-6_10
  • Saatsi, Juha and Alexander Reutlinger, 2018, “Taking Reductionism to the Limit: How to Rebut the Antireductionist Argument from Infinite Limits”, Philosophy of Science , 85(3): 455–482. doi:10.1086/697735
  • Salis, Fiora, forthcoming, “The New Fiction View of Models”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , first online: 20 April 2019. doi:10.1093/bjps/axz015
  • Salmon, Wesley C., 1984, Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Schaffner, Kenneth F., 1969, “The Watson–Crick Model and Reductionism”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 20(4): 325–348. doi:10.1093/bjps/20.4.325
  • Scheibe, Erhard, 1997, Die Reduktion physikalischer Theorien: Ein Beitrag zur Einheit der Physik, Teil I: Grundlagen und elementare Theorie , Berlin: Springer.
  • –––, 1999, Die Reduktion physikalischer Theorien: Ein Beitrag zur Einheit der Physik, Teil II: Inkommensurabilität und Grenzfallreduktion , Berlin: Springer.
  • –––, 2001, Between Rationalism and Empiricism: Selected Papers in the Philosophy of Physics , Brigitte Falkenburg (ed.), New York: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-1-4613-0183-7
  • Shanks, Niall (ed.), 1998, Idealization in Contemporary Physics , Amsterdam: Rodopi.
  • Shech, Elay, 2018, “Idealizations, Essential Self-Adjointness, and Minimal Model Explanation in the Aharonov–Bohm Effect”, Synthese , 195(11): 4839–4863. doi:10.1007/s11229-017-1428-6
  • Sismondo, Sergio and Snait Gissis (eds.), 1999, Modeling and Simulation , Special Issue of Science in Context , 12(2).
  • Sorensen, Roy A., 1992, Thought Experiments , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/019512913X.001.0001
  • Spector, Marshall, 1965, “Models and Theories”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 16(62): 121–142. doi:10.1093/bjps/XVI.62.121
  • Staley, Kent W., 2004, The Evidence for the Top Quark: Objectivity and Bias in Collaborative Experimentation , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Sterrett, Susan G., 2006, “Models of Machines and Models of Phenomena”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science , 20(1): 69–80. doi:10.1080/02698590600641024
  • –––, forthcoming, “Scale Modeling”, in Diane Michelfelder and Neelke Doorn (eds.), Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Engineering , Chapter 32. [ Sterrett forthcoming available online ]
  • Strevens, Michael, 2004, “The Causal and Unification Approaches to Explanation Unified—Causally”, Noûs , 38(1): 154–176. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2004.00466.x
  • –––, 2008, Depth: An Account of Scientific Explanation , Cambridge, MA, and London: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 2013, Tychomancy: Inferring Probability from Causal Structure , Cambridge, MA, and London: Harvard University Press.
  • Suárez, Mauricio, 2003, “Scientific Representation: Against Similarity and Isomorphism”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science , 17(3): 225–244. doi:10.1080/0269859032000169442
  • –––, 2004, “An Inferential Conception of Scientific Representation”, Philosophy of Science , 71(5): 767–779. doi:10.1086/421415
  • ––– (ed.), 2009, Fictions in Science: Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealization , London: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203890103
  • Sugden, Robert, 2000, “Credible Worlds: The Status of Theoretical Models in Economics”, Journal of Economic Methodology , 7(1): 1–31. doi:10.1080/135017800362220
  • Sullivan, Emily and Kareem Khalifa, 2019, “Idealizations and Understanding: Much Ado About Nothing?”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy , 97(4): 673–689. doi:10.1080/00048402.2018.1564337
  • Suppe, Frederick, 2000, “Theory Identity”, in William H. Newton-Smith (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Science , Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 525–527.
  • Suppes, Patrick, 1960, “A Comparison of the Meaning and Uses of Models in Mathematics and the Empirical Sciences”, Synthese , 12(2–3): 287–301. Reprinted in Freudenthal 1961: 163–177, and in Suppes 1969: 10–23. doi:10.1007/BF00485107 doi:10.1007/978-94-010-3667-2_16
  • –––, 1962, “Models of Data”, in Ernest Nagel, Patrick Suppes, and Alfred Tarski (eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science: Proceedings of the 1960 International Congress , Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, pp. 252–261. Reprinted in Suppes 1969: 24–35.
  • –––, 1969, Studies in the Methodology and Foundations of Science: Selected Papers from 1951 to 1969 , Dordrecht: Reidel.
  • –––, 2007, “Statistical Concepts in Philosophy of Science”, Synthese , 154(3): 485–496. doi:10.1007/s11229-006-9122-0
  • Swoyer, Chris, 1991, “Structural Representation and Surrogative Reasoning”, Synthese , 87(3): 449–508. doi:10.1007/BF00499820
  • Tabor, Michael, 1989, Chaos and Integrability in Nonlinear Dynamics: An Introduction , New York: John Wiley.
  • Teller, Paul, 2001, “Twilight of the Perfect Model”, Erkenntnis , 55(3): 393–415. doi:10.1023/A:1013349314515
  • –––, 2002, “Critical Study: Nancy Cartwright’s The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science ”, Noûs , 36(4): 699–725. doi:10.1111/1468-0068.t01-1-00408
  • –––, 2009, “Fictions, Fictionalization, and Truth in Science”, in Suárez 2009: 235–247.
  • –––, 2018, “Referential and Perspectival Realism”, Spontaneous Generations: A Journal for the History and Philosophy of Science , 9(1): 151–164. doi:10.4245/sponge.v9i1.26990
  • Tešić, Marko, 2019, “Confirmation and the Generalized Nagel–Schaffner Model of Reduction: A Bayesian Analysis”, Synthese , 196(3): 1097–1129. doi:10.1007/s11229-017-1501-1
  • Thomasson, Amie L., 1999, Fiction and Metaphysics , New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511527463
  • –––, 2020, “If Models Were Fictions, Then What Would They Be?”, in Levy and Godfrey-Smith 2020: 51–74.
  • Thomson-Jones, Martin, 2006, “Models and the Semantic View”, Philosophy of Science , 73(5): 524–535. doi:10.1086/518322
  • –––, 2020, “Realism about Missing Systems”, in Levy and Godfrey-Smith 2020: 75–101.
  • Toon, Adam, 2012, Models as Make-Believe: Imagination, Fiction and Scientific Representation , Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Trout, J. D., 2002, “Scientific Explanation and the Sense of Understanding”, Philosophy of Science , 69(2): 212–233. doi:10.1086/341050
  • van Fraassen, Bas C., 1989, Laws and Symmetry , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0198248601.001.0001
  • Walton, Kendall L., 1990, Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Weisberg, Michael, 2007, “Three Kinds of Idealization”, Journal of Philosophy , 104(12): 639–659. doi:10.5840/jphil20071041240
  • –––, 2013, Simulation and Similarity: Using Models to Understand the World , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199933662.001.0001
  • Weisberg, Michael and Ryan Muldoon, 2009, “Epistemic Landscapes and the Division of Cognitive Labor”, Philosophy of Science , 76(2): 225–252. doi:10.1086/644786
  • Wimsatt, William, 1987, “False Models as Means to Truer Theories”, in Matthew Nitecki and Antoni Hoffman (eds.), Neutral Models in Biology , Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 23–55.
  • –––, 2007, Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations to Reality , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Woodward, James, 2003, Making Things Happen: A Theory of Causal Explanation , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0195155270.001.0001
  • Woody, Andrea I., 2004, “More Telltale Signs: What Attention to Representation Reveals about Scientific Explanation”, Philosophy of Science , 71(5): 780–793. doi:10.1086/421416
  • Zollman, Kevin J. S., 2007, “The Communication Structure of Epistemic Communities”, Philosophy of Science , 74(5): 574–587. doi:10.1086/525605
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy article on models
  • Bibliography (1450–2008), Mueller Science
  • Interactive models from various sciences (Phet, University of Colorado, Boulder)
  • Models of the global climate (Climate.gov)
  • Double-helix model of DNA (Proteopedia)
  • A Biologist’s Guide to Mathematical Modeling in Ecology and Evolution (Sarah Otto and Troy Day)
  • Lotka–Volterra model (analyticphysics.com)
  • Schelling’s Model of Segregation (Frank McCown)
  • Modeling Commons (NetLogo)
  • Social and Economic Networks: Models and Analysis (Stanford Online course)
  • Neural Network Models (TensorFlow)

analogy and analogical reasoning | laws of nature | science: unity of | scientific explanation | scientific realism | scientific representation | scientific theories: structure of | simulations in science | thought experiments

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Joe Dewhurst, James Nguyen, Alexander Reutlinger, Collin Rice, Dunja Šešelja, and Paul Teller for helpful comments on the drafts of the revised version in 2019. When writing the original version back in 2006 we benefitted from comments and suggestions by Nancy Cartwright, Paul Humphreys, Julian Reiss, Elliott Sober, Chris Swoyer, and Paul Teller.

Copyright © 2020 by Roman Frigg < r . p . frigg @ lse . ac . uk > Stephan Hartmann < stephan . hartmann @ lrz . uni-muenchen . de >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Purdue Online Writing Lab Purdue OWL® College of Liberal Arts

Welcome to the Purdue Online Writing Lab

OWL logo

Welcome to the Purdue OWL

This page is brought to you by the OWL at Purdue University. When printing this page, you must include the entire legal notice.

Copyright ©1995-2018 by The Writing Lab & The OWL at Purdue and Purdue University. All rights reserved. This material may not be published, reproduced, broadcast, rewritten, or redistributed without permission. Use of this site constitutes acceptance of our terms and conditions of fair use.

The Online Writing Lab at Purdue University houses writing resources and instructional material, and we provide these as a free service of the Writing Lab at Purdue. Students, members of the community, and users worldwide will find information to assist with many writing projects. Teachers and trainers may use this material for in-class and out-of-class instruction.

The Purdue On-Campus Writing Lab and Purdue Online Writing Lab assist clients in their development as writers—no matter what their skill level—with on-campus consultations, online participation, and community engagement. The Purdue Writing Lab serves the Purdue, West Lafayette, campus and coordinates with local literacy initiatives. The Purdue OWL offers global support through online reference materials and services.

A Message From the Assistant Director of Content Development 

The Purdue OWL® is committed to supporting  students, instructors, and writers by offering a wide range of resources that are developed and revised with them in mind. To do this, the OWL team is always exploring possibilties for a better design, allowing accessibility and user experience to guide our process. As the OWL undergoes some changes, we welcome your feedback and suggestions by email at any time.

Please don't hesitate to contact us via our contact page  if you have any questions or comments.

All the best,

Social Media

Facebook twitter.

The use of scientific methods and models in the philosophy of science

  • Published: 05 February 2024
  • Volume 129 , pages 1255–1276, ( 2024 )

Cite this article

essay model science

  • Rafael Ventura   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-3708-4709 1  

426 Accesses

Explore all metrics

What is the relation between philosophy of science and the sciences? As Pradeu et al. (British Journal for the Philosophy of Science https://doi.org/10.1086/715518 , 2021) and Khelfaoui et al. (Synthese 199:6219, 2021) recently show, part of this relation is constituted by “philosophy in science”: the use of philosophical methods to address questions in the sciences. But another part is what one might call “science in philosophy”: the use of methods drawn from the sciences to tackle philosophical questions. In this paper, we focus on one class of such methods and examine the role that model-based methods play within “science in philosophy”. To do this, we first build a bibliographic coupling network with Web of Science records of all papers published in philosophy of science journals from 2000 to 2020 ( \(N=9217\) ). After detecting the most prominent communities of papers in the network, we use a supervised classifier to identify all papers that use model-based methods. Drawing on work in cultural evolution, we also propose a model to represent the evolution of methods in each one of these communities. Finally, we measure the strength of cultural selection for model-based methods during the given time period by integrating model and data. Results indicate not only that model-based methods have had a significant presence in philosophy of science over the last two decades, but also that there is considerable variation in their use across communities. Results further indicate that some communities have experienced strong selection for the use of model-based methods but that other have not; we validate this finding with a logistic regression of paper methodology on publication year. We conclude by discussing some implications of our findings and suggest that model-based methods play an increasingly important role within “science in philosophy” in some but not all areas of philosophy of science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price includes VAT (Russian Federation)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Rent this article via DeepDyve

Institutional subscriptions

essay model science

Similar content being viewed by others

essay model science

Literature reviews as independent studies: guidelines for academic practice

essay model science

Scientific Truth in a Post-Truth Era: A Review*

essay model science

How to Write and Publish a Research Paper for a Peer-Reviewed Journal

Ainsworth, P. (2011). Ontic structural realism and the principle of the identity of indiscernibles. Erkenntnis, 75 (1), 67–84.

MathSciNet   Google Scholar  

Alspector-Kelly, M. (2011). Why safety doesn’t save closure. Synthese, 183 (2), 127–142.

Bangu, S. (2013). Indispensability and explanation. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64 (2), 255–277.

Barrett, J. A. (2014). Description and the problem of priors. Erkenntnis, 79 (6), 1343–1353.

Biddle, J. (2013). State of the field: Transient underdetermination and values in science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 44 (1), 124–133.

Google Scholar  

Blondel, V. D., Guillaume, J.-L., Lambiotte, R., & Lefebvre, E. (2008). Fast unfolding of communities in large networks. Journal of statistical mechanics: Theory and Experiment, 2008 (10), P10008.

Bokulich, A. (2003). Horizontal models: From bakers to cats. Philosophy of Science, 70 (3), 609–627.

Bolker, B. M. (2008). Ecological models and data in R . Princeton University Press.

Bonino, G., Maffezioli, P., Petrovich, E., & Tripodi, P. (2022). When philosophy (of science) meets formal methods: A citation analysis of early approaches between research fields. Synthese, 200 (2), 177.

Boyack, K., Börner, K., & Klavans, R. (2009). Mapping the structure and evolution of chemistry research. Scientometrics, 79 (1), 45–60.

Bright, L. K. (2017). On fraud. Philosophical Studies, 174 (2), 291–310.

Brössel, P. (2015). Keynes’s coefficient of dependence revisited. Erkenntnis, 80 (3), 521–553.

Bruner, J. P. (2013). Policing epistemic communities. Episteme, 10 (4), 403.

Byron, J. M. (2007). Whence philosophy of biology? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58 (3), 409–422.

Chandrasekar, P. and Qian, K. (2016). The impact of data preprocessing on the performance of a naive bayes classifier. In 2016 IEEE 40th Annual Computer Software and Applications Conference (COMPSAC) , volume 2, pp. 618–619. IEEE.

Clatterbuck, H. (2015). Drift beyond Wright-Fisher. Synthese, 192 (11), 3487–3507.

Doppelt, G. (2005). Empirical success or explanatory success: What does current scientific realism need to explain? Philosophy of Science, 72 (5), 1076–1087.

Ducheyne, S. (2012). Scientific representations as limiting cases. Erkenntnis, 76 (1), 73–89.

Eck, N. J., & Waltman, L. (2009). How to normalize cooccurrence data? An analysis of some well-known similarity measures. Journal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology, 60 (8), 1635–1651.

Fagan, M. B. (2012). The joint account of mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 79 (4), 448–472.

Fletcher, S. C., Knobe, J., Wheeler, G., & Woodcock, B. A. (2021). Changing use of formal methods in philosophy: Late 2000s vs. late 2010s. Synthese, 199 , 14555.

Frigg, R., Nguyen, J., et al. (2020). Modelling nature: An opinionated introduction to scientific representation . Springer.

Gelfert, A. (2011). Mathematical formalisms in scientific practice: From denotation to model-based representation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42 (2), 272–286.

Glänzel, W., & Thijs, B. (2017). Using hybrid methods and ‘core documents’ for the representation of clusters and topics: The astronomy dataset. Scientometrics, 111 , 1071–1087.

Griffiths, P. E., & Stotz, K. (2008). Experimental philosophy of science. Philosophy Compass, 3 (3), 507–521.

Heesen, R. (2019). The credit incentive to be a maverick. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 76 , 5–12.

Hopcroft, J., Khan, O., Kulis, B., & Selman, B. (2004). Tracking evolving communities in large linked networks. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 101 (suppl–1), 5249–5253.

Huang, L., Cai, Y., Zhao, E., Zhang, S., Shu, Y., & Fan, J. (2022). Measuring the interdisciplinarity of information and library science interactions using citation analysis and semantic analysis. Scientometrics, 127 , 6733.

Huggett, N., & Wüthrich, C. (2018). The (a) temporal emergence of spacetime. Philosophy of Science, 85 (5), 1190–1203.

Karsdorp, F., Manjavacas, E., Fonteyn, L., & Kestemont, M. (2020). Classifying evolutionary forces in language change using neural networks. Evolutionary Human Sciences, 2 , e50.

Kessler, M. M. (1963). Bibliographic coupling between scientific papers. American Documentation, 14 (1), 10–25.

Khelfaoui, M., Gingras, Y., Lemoine, M., & Pradeu, T. (2021). The visibility of philosophy of science in the sciences, 1980–2018. Synthese, 199 , 6219.

Knobe, J. (2007). Experimental philosophy. Philosophy Compass, 2 (1), 81–92.

Kochiras, H. (2011). Gravity’s cause and substance counting: Contextualizing the problems. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42 (1), 167–184.

Kulvicki, J. (2007). What is what it’s like? Introducing perceptual modes of presentation. Synthese, 156 (2), 205–229.

Leitgeb, H. (2013). Scientific philosophy, mathematical philosophy, and all that. Metaphilosophy, 44 (3), 267–275.

Levins, R. (1966). The strategy of model building in population biology. American Scientist, 54 (4), 421–431.

Lewis, P. J. (2007). Empty waves in Bohmian quantum mechanics. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58 (4), 787–803.

Machery, E. (2016). Experimental philosophy of science. A Companion to Experimental Philosophy . https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118661666.ch33

Article   Google Scholar  

Machery, E., & Cohen, K. (2012). An evidence-based study of the evolutionary behavioral sciences. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63 (1), 177–226.

Malaterre, C., Chartier, J.-F., & Pulizzotto, D. (2019). What is this thing called philosophy of science? A computational topic-modeling perspective, 1934–2015. HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, 9 (2), 215–249.

Malaterre, C., Lareau, F., Pulizzotto, D., & St-Onge, J. (2021). Eight journals over eight decades: A computational topic-modeling approach to contemporary philosophy of science. Synthese, 199 (1), 2883–2923.

Malaterre, C., Pulizzotto, D., & Lareau, F. (2020). Revisiting three decades of biology and philosophy: A computational topic-modeling perspective. Biology & Philosophy, 35 (1), 1–25.

Martini, C., & Pinto, M. F. (2017). Modeling the social organization of science. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 7 (2), 221–238.

Mayo-Wilson, C., & Zollman, K. J. (2021). The computational philosophy: Simulation as a core philosophical method. Synthese, 199 , 3647.

McCallum, A., Nigam, K., et al. (1998). A comparison of event models for naive Bayes text classification. AAAI-98 Workshop on Learning for Text Categorization, 752 (1), 41–48.

Mizrahi, M. and Dickinson, M. (2020). Argumentation in philosophical practice: An empirical study. In Evidence, Persuasion & Diversity. Proceedings of OSSA 12, 3–6 June 2020 .

Moretti, F. (2000). Conjectures on world literature. New Left Review, 1 , 54.

Newberry, M. G., Ahern, C. A., Clark, R., & Plotkin, J. B. (2017). Detecting evolutionary forces in language change. Nature, 551 (7679), 223–226.

Noichl, M. (2021). Modeling the structure of recent philosophy. Synthese, 198 (6), 5089–5100.

O’Connor, C. (2019). The natural selection of conservative science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 76 , 24–29.

Oreskes, N., Stainforth, D. A., & Smith, L. A. (2010). Adaptation to global warming: Do climate models tell us what we need to know? Philosophy of Science, 77 (5), 1012–1028.

Overton, J. A. (2013). “Explain” in scientific discourse. Synthese, 190 (8), 1383–1405.

Pence, C. H., & Ramsey, G. (2018). How to do digital philosophy of science. Philosophy of Science, 85 (5), 930–941.

Pradeu, T., Lemoine, M., Khelfaoui, M., & Gingras, Y. (2021). Philosophy in science: Can philosophers of science permeate through science and produce scientific knowledge? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science . https://doi.org/10.1086/715518

Ramsey, G. (2013). Organisms, traits, and population subdivisions: Two arguments against the causal conception of fitness? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64 (3), 589–608.

Ramsey, G., & De Block, A. (2017). Is cultural fitness hopelessly confused? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 68 (2), 305–328.

Ramsey, G., & De Block, A. (2021). The Dynamics of Science: Computational Frontiers in History and Philosophy of Science . Pittsburgh University Press.

Renne, B. (2008). Public and private communication are different: Results on relative expressivity. Synthese, 165 (2), 225–245.

Romasanta, A. K. S., van der Sijde, P., & van Muijlwijk-Koezen, J. (2020). Innovation in pharmaceutical r &d: Mapping the research landscape. Scientometrics, 125 , 1801–1832.

Shaw, J. R. (2013). De se belief and rational choice. Synthese, 190 (3), 491–508.

Sindi, S. S., & Dale, R. (2016). Culturomics as a data playground for tests of selection: Mathematical approaches to detecting selection in word use. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 405 , 140–149.

Sprenger, J., & Hartmann, S. (2019). Bayesian philosophy of science . Oxford University Press.

Suárez, M. (2008). Fictions in science: Philosophical essays on modeling and idealization . Routledge.

Tanaka, M. M., Godfrey-Smith, P., & Kerr, B. (2020). The dual landscape model of adaptation and niche construction. Philosophy of Science, 87 (3), 478–498.

Thicke, M. (2020). Evaluating formal models of science. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 51 (2), 315–335.

Thijs, B., Zhang, L., & Glänzel, W. (2015). Bibliographic coupling and hierarchical clustering for the validation and improvement of subject-classification schemes. Scientometrics, 105 , 1453–1467.

Tugby, M. (2021). Grounding theories of powers. Synthese, 198 (12), 11187–11216.

Weatherall, J. O., O’Connor, C., & Bruner, J. P. (2020). How to beat science and influence people: Policymakers and propaganda in epistemic networks. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 71 (4), 1157–1186.

Weingart, S. B. (2015). Finding the history and philosophy of science. Erkenntnis, 80 (1), 201–213.

Weisberg, M. (2007). Three kinds of idealization. The Journal of Philosophy, 104 (12), 639–659.

Weisberg, M. (2012). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world . Oxford University Press.

Weisberg, M., & Muldoon, R. (2009). Epistemic landscapes and the division of cognitive labor. Philosophy of Science, 76 (2), 225–252.

Wheeler, G. (2013). Models, models, and models. Metaphilosophy, 44 (3), 293–300.

Wray, K. B. (2010). Philosophy of science: What are the key journals in the field? Erkenntnis, 72 (3), 423–430.

Wray, K. B., & Bornmann, L. (2015). Philosophy of science viewed through the lense of “referenced publication years spectroscopy”(RPYS). Scientometrics, 102 , 1987–1996.

Wright, S. (1931). Evolution in mendelian populations. Genetics, 16 (2), 97.

Zollman, K. J. (2007). The communication structure of epistemic communities. Philosophy of Science, 74 (5), 574–587.

Zollman, K. J. (2018). The credit economy and the economic rationality of science. The Journal of Philosophy, 115 (1), 5–33.

Download references

Acknowledgements

A pre-print version of this paper is available at http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/20885/ . Special thanks to Thomas Pradeu, Charles Pence, Kevin Zollman, and many others for very helpful feedback on earlier versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

University of Pennsylvania, 112 Leidy Labs,3740 Hamilton Walk, Philadelphia, PA, 19104, USA

Rafael Ventura

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rafael Ventura .

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest.

There is no conflict of interest to declare.

Additional information

Publisher's note.

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix 1: Naive Bayes classifier

To label papers with respect to their methodology, we used a multinomial naive Bayes classifier. Naive Bayes classifiers assign an item to a class by maximizing the following expression:

where \(Pr(q_i|w_1,..., w_m)\) is the probability of the item belonging to class \(q_i\) given that the item has features \(w_1,..., w_m\) , \(Pr(q_i)\) is the unconditional probability of the class, and \(Pr(w_1,..., w_m)\) is the unconditional probability of the features. Items correspond to papers, classes correspond to the two types of methods that a paper might use (model-based method vs. no model-based method), and features correspond to the number of times that a word occurred in a paper’s abstract and the number of times that a last name appears in a paper’s reference section. These numbers are integers because words can appear any number of times in the abstract and last names can appear any number of times in the reference section.

Appendix 2: Wright-Fisher model

To build a model for the cultural evolution of methods in philosophy of science, we assumed that papers are chosen to reproduce in proportion to how many papers of each type were available in the previous year. The probability that an individual of a given type—say, papers that use model-based methods—will be chosen to reproduce is given by:

where \(i_{t}\) is the number of papers of that type in generation t , \(j_{t} = N_{t} - i_{t}\) is the number of individuals of the other type, and s is the selection coefficient measuring the strength of selection. Generations correspond to publication years. The parameter s is positive when selection favors the focal type, negative when selection favors the non-focal type, and zero when selection does not favor any type.

Conversely, the probability that a paper of the other type—papers that do not use model-based methods—will be chosen to reproduce is given by:

where terms are defined as before.

Further, we assume that the population of papers grows over time because papers never leave the publication record. The probability that a population with \(i_{t}\) papers of a given type in generation t transitions to a population with \(i_{t+1}\) individuals of the same type in generation \(t+1\) is thus given by:

where \({ N_{t+1} - N_{t} \atopwithdelims ()i_{t+1} - i_{t} }\) is the number of combinations we can obtain by choosing \(i_{t+1} - i_{t}\) individuals of the focal type in a group of \(N_{t+1} - N_{t}\) individuals, \(p^{ i_{t+1}-i_{t} }\) is the probability that \(i_{t+1} - i_{t}\) individuals of the focal type will be chosen to enter the population, and \(q^{ j_{t+1}-j_{t} }\) is the probability that \(j_{t+1} - j_{t}\) individuals of the non-focal type will be chosen to enter the population. Expression ( 4 ) therefore gives the probability that a population with \(i_{t}\) papers of a given type will transition to a population with \(i_{t+1}\) individuals of the same type by growing from size \(N_{t}\) to size \(N_{t+1}\) .

Appendix 3: Maximum-likelihood estimation

To estimate the strength of selection ( s ) for or against the use of model-based methods, we used the technique of maximum-likelihood estimation. That is, we take \(\hat{s}\) be the value that maximizes the following expression:

where \(\hat{s}\) is the maximum-likelihood estimate of selection for or against the use of model-based methods in a particular community, \(Pr(i_{t+1}|i_{t})\) is given by expression ( 4 ), and the sum is over the entire time period considered here—namely, from 2000 to 2020. Note that we take the log of \(Pr(i_{t+1}|i_{t})\) simply to facilitate computation, as values for \(Pr(i_{t+1}|i_{t})\) can be very small. Note also that equation ( 5 ) correspond to the estimate of selection for a particular community, so \(\hat{s}\) must be estimated separately for each community of papers.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Ventura, R. The use of scientific methods and models in the philosophy of science. Scientometrics 129 , 1255–1276 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11192-024-04931-6

Download citation

Received : 24 December 2022

Accepted : 08 January 2024

Published : 05 February 2024

Issue Date : March 2024

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/s11192-024-04931-6

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Philosophy of science
  • Bibliographic network
  • Cultural evolution
  • Metascience
  • Find a journal
  • Publish with us
  • Track your research
  • Advanced search
  • Peer review

essay model science

To submit your Book proposal, please click here

  • Record : found
  • Abstract : found
  • Book : found

Economics : Model Essays (Second Edition)

essay model science

Read this book at

  • Review book
  • Invite someone to review

Economics: Model Essays is the 2nd edition of the best-selling revision guide that helps students gain a strong grade in the essay component of the 2023–2025 Cambridge International AS & A Level Economics (9708) examination paper. With over 50 new model essays, the book provides a clear essay structure for each essay, various tips, and conceptual diagrams on basic economics concepts to give an overall insight into each subject topic.

Related collections

' class=

Sunway University Press

' class=

Author and book information

Comment on this book, similar content 287 .

  • “Tsar and God” : and Other Essays in Russian Cultural Semiotics Authors: Boris Uspensky , Victor Zhivov , Marcus C. Levitt
  • Intraventricular mass lesions at magnetic resonance imaging: iconographic essay - part 1* Authors: Felipe de Castro , Fabiano Reis , José Guerra
  • Analysis on the nexus amid CO2 emissions, energy intensity, economic growth, and foreign direct investment in Belt and Road economies: does the level of income matter? Authors: Olivier Abban , Jiying Wu , Isaac Mensah

essay model science

Essay – examples & model answers | C1 Advanced (CAE)

essay model science

CAE Essay Example & Model Answer:  Younger people

Example exam task:.

Your class has listened to a radio discussion about how adults can be a good influence on younger people. You have made the notes below:

Some opinions expressed in the discussion:

Write an  essay  discussing only  two points . You should  explain which point is more important , giving reasons in support of your answer.

CAE Essay: Example Answer (Grade: 3-4)

Example answer:.

Adults can influence younger people in a good way, but also in a bad way. There are various possibilities how this can happen.

On the one hand, setting a good example is a quite useful way, because younger people will be able to see the adult’s behaviours and ways of thinking. They will see and feel the adult’s values and lives and may decide to become like them someday or at least to try to behave and think like adults.

On the other hand, offering advices seems to be the better way for me, how adults can influence younger people. Because, setting a good example to follow can be useful, but it also is pretty exhausting for adults and they may have some pressure as well. In addition, it’s just an opportunity for younger people, because they’ll decide rather they want to become like these adults or not.

In my opinion, younger people should try to learn how life works on their own. This will lead to more failures, but in my opinion, failing is normal and necessary. Of course this way of influencing is more exhausting for younger people, but I guess they’ll figure out how to do things on their own.

Failures are crucial for learning and for success, therefore I think that adults just should offer advices and show them, that they believe in them. That’s going to encourage younger people and they will try to learn and believe in themselves. That’s why I think, that offering advices is the better way how adults can influence younger people.

FCE, CAE, CPE

Practice, write & improve, examiners comments & grade:.

5 All content is relevant and the target reader is fully informed.

3The essay is written using the conventions of the communicative task effectively. The essay has a neutral tone and uses appropriate phrases to introduce and connect ideas through the text (On theone hand; On the other hand; In my opinion).

The essay topic is clearly communicated in the first paragraph and the main points are developed in separate paragraphs.

However, there are a couple of slips in the register (I guess they’ll figure out; pretty exhausting). The conclusion restates the candidate’s own opinion about which way is better, after giving some examples to support their view.

3The text is well organised and coherent. The structure of the essay is logical and cohesive devices are used to connect the ideas within and across sentences.

Organisational patterns are used to generally good effect. In the latter part of the essay, failure is discussed (in my opinion, failing is normal and necessary) and then the effects of failure on young people are explored. The idea of failing is repeated in the final paragraph (Failures are crucial) to support the candidate’s conclusion.

2There is a range of vocabulary used appropriately, but there is some awkwardness of expression at times, either due to word choice or word order.

Some grammatical forms are used with control, such as present tenses and modals, but there are errors when more complex forms or expressions are attempted.

CAE Essay: Model Answer (Grade: 4-5)

Many parents, struggle with bringing up their child into be responsible adults and are unsure how to influence them. There are of course, many ways of influencing young adults, and I want to present and discuss two of them: giving rules to obey and offering your children advice.

First of all, it has to be said that advice is easy to ignore, and that children especially in their adolescent years, don’t even want advice, and will tell you so, too: ‘I don’t need your help’, they will say to you or even shout at you. Kids often feel misunderstood they think their parents can’t understand them, because they are ‘too old’. If your son or daughter has a problem, it is important to make him or her feel that you do understand and only want their best and are, therefore, offering some advice, hoping it will help them.

Then again, there are rules. Rules can be placed differently, they don’t need to be a stone-hard barrier to your child’s freedom. Adolescents will often bend rules or utterly break them all because they need this certain feeling of rebellion and freedom. Rules also help the maturing of the conscience. If a child doesn’t need to follow rules, it’s conscience will never mature and it will not know wrong from right. If, however you place rules, and punishments should they not be followed, your son or daughter will learn not to steal, to be home on time simply because he or she doesn’t want to be punished. Don’t overdo it, though. Placing too hard punishments could also lead to destruction of the conscience your child never being able to make it’s own decisions.

I think that giving rules to obey is the best way of influencing young people. Wherever you go, you find certain rules. Not every rule is absolutely sensible, but while growing older, your child will learn by itself which rules should be followed and will follow them of free choice.

5All content is relevant and the target reader is fully informed.

The candidate chooses two of the ways adults can influence younger people Negative aspects of both choices are described and this is balanced with a more positive aspect of each option.

In the conclusion, the candidate offers their own opinion on which way is more effective and explains why.


4Essay-writing conventions are used effectively to communicate ideas clearly. The register is mostly consistent despite the candidate offering advice. Overall the language of explanation, opinion and justification is appropriate for this essay and holds the reader’s attention.

There is a mix of straightforward and complex ideas running through the paragraphs.

4The text is well organised and coherent, and the candidate makes good use of a variety of cohesive devices to show connections between ideas across sentences and paragraphs, including referencing, punctuation and conjunctions.

More complex organisational patterns are used to generally good effect, particularly when presenting positive and negative aspects of one topic.

4There is a range of vocabulary, including less common lexis which is used effectively.

There is a range of simple and more complex grammatical forms which are used with control and flexibility. There are occasional errors but these do not impede communication and are sometimes due to ambition or are slips.

CAE Essay Model Answer: Crimes

You have watched a documentary about what causes young people to start committing crimes. You have made the notes below.

Some opinions expressed in the documentary:

The documentary investigated what makes young people commit crimes. It seems to me that the most important reason is lack of appropriate control by parents.

To put the blame for youth crime on parents may seem rather unfair, but a lot of the interviews and information in the documentary backed up this belief. There is more than one reason why many parents fail to control their children. Some parents believe that it is wrong to discipline children in any way, and think that children should be free to do whatever they want. Some parents are simply too lazy and selfish to control their children, preferring to let them behave badly so that they can continue doing what they want. Another reason is that some parents did not grow up being disciplined by their parents and so they do not do that with their own children.

Factors such as economic position and influence from peers can of course play a major role in causing young people to turn to crime. However, it is my view that how children am brought up is more important than either of those. They need firm rules to be given to them by parents who they respect, and if they are not given firm guidance by parents, some of them are bound to behave badly. Some of this bad behaviour will be criminal. If you do something wrong and you get away with it, you will do it again or do worse things.

CAE Essay Model Answer: Talent Shows

Your class has attended a panel discussion on the subject of TV shows that feature members of the public, such as reality TV shows and talent competitions. You have made the notes below.

Some opinions expressed in the discussion:

The discussion focused on various issues connected with TV shows that feature members of the public. They have been a worldwide phenomenon for some time and views on them vary greatly.

One of the main aspects of these shows is the entertainment they provide for viewers. Obviously, they would not be watched by so many people if audiences didn’t find them entertaining. During the discussion. It was said that the shows are enjoyable to watch and do no harm. People enjoy watching ordinary members of the public living their lives, doing their jobs or taking part In talent competitions because they can relate to those people. I think that this 15 true. Although I don’t personally find them interesting and therefore seldom watch them, I agree that many people find them very entertaining.

However, a morn serious aspect was discussed and that Is the Influence these shows can have on people. especially young people. This, I think, Is the most Important aspect. Many young people are Influenced by these shows and the people on then They too want to appear on TV, to be ‘famousjust like the people they see. Rather than thinking realistically about their futures and about getting jobs and careers. they get the Impression that anyone can be famous. Instead of focusing on building a life in a practical way, they dream of being like those people on the shows. I think this 15 the most important consequence of these shows and It is a harmful one.

CAE Essay Example & Model Answer: Facilities

Your class has attended a panel discussion on facilities that should receive money from local authorities. You have made the notes below:

Some opinions expressed in the discussion:

Facilities in need of funds

Having listened to today’s radio programme about facilities that need financial help, I realised that sports centers and public gardens have been neglected over the years by the local authorities.

There are few sports centers out there that meet the right characteristics that a good sports center must have. This is one of the many reasons that people avoid sport. We see lots of kids nowadays suffering from obesity and other health problems caused by the simple fact that they don’t do sport.

Another reason for this is that people have nowhere to go out for a walk or to run in a nice place. Public gardens, parks for example are also lacking in numbers. The ones that are already there are not very nice and they don’t look very good. I think that by improving this two facilities the population can benefit from this. By creating more sports centers, there will be some more jobs offered, and some kids might even follow a sports career. By making more public gardens people can get out more often and spend some good quality time relaxing.

I think that local authorities should invest money in both facilities because, this is a good way to increase the populations health.

3All content is relevant to the task and the target reader is on the whole informed. The candidate has not made a final selection between the two facilities.

4The conventions of essay writing are evident and the target reader’s attention is held throughout. The opening statement sets up the context of the essay, and the candidate chooses two of the facilities to discuss (parks and sports centres). The candidate links these two aspects throughout the essay, and this linking is effective in communicating more complex ideas which relate to both facilities.

A consistent register is used, and the overall tone is suitably persuasive and objective.

4The text is well organised and coherent. Fairly subtle organisational patterns and cohesive devices are used, rather than overt linking words: for example, relative clauses/pronouns, substitution and ellipsis.

Some sentences are quite short and could have been connected to make the text more fluid at times.

3There is a range of vocabulary and some less common lexis, which is collocated appropriately.

There is also a range of simple and more complex grammatical structures used
with control.

Example Answer:

In regard of a recent discussion about the facilities, which are financially supported by local authorities, I would like to write a few of my personal thoughts. Whether we are talking about sports centres or public gardens, there is no doubt that they are both a good thing to have in the city and should both be supported somehow. The only question then is which one of these is more important, what are the pros and cons of each one?

Let me start with the sport centres as I think these are a bit more problematic. Obviously, in our times where lots of people spend days sitting in their office staring at a computer, some sort of physical training is very important. We have to balance that shift in our lifestyles. The problem I see with supporting the sports centres is the number of activities that you can do at these days. There is almost countless list of either individual or team sports that we can think of, and each centre is usually designed for a specific type or at least a group of sports similar in its nature. Therefore I think that it is too difficult to support them equally and we can’t say which activity is better than the others either. Another reason for not financing sports as much as green parks is their commercial use. What I mean by that is that we usually pay for everything the centre offers us to do and therefore they are more able to last from their own money than gardens.

Regarding of the green spaces, the situation is much clearer I think. Every city needs gardens where people can sit and relax, but nobody is going to pay a tax for just walking around.

These factors lead me to my conclusion, that the public gardens are definitely a facility which should be financed from public money, whereas in the case of sports centres, the situation is questionable.

5All content is relevant to the task and the target reader would be fully informed. The candidate discusses two of the options (sports centres and green spaces).

4The conventions of the communicative task are used effectively, holding the target reader’s attention with ease. The register and tone are consistent and the language choices are sufficiently formal and appropriate throughout, particularly the opening and closing paragraphs.
4The essay is well organised and coherent, and the different ideas are clearly signposted throughout. The target reader can easily follow the argument. The paragraphs are internally well constructed and are linked together appropriately. In terms of organisational patterns, the overall effect is generally good, rather than good throughout, due to the imbalance of length between the second and third paragraphs.
4A range of vocabulary, including less common lexis, is used effectively, although not always precisely. A wide range of simple and complex grammatical forms is used with control and flexibility, particularly in terms of sentence construction. Although there are occasional errors, these are often slips and do not impede communication.

engxam logo english exams

Would you pass C1 Advanced (CAE)?

Essay on Science for Students and Children

500+ words essay on science.

Essay on science:  As we look back in our ancient times we see so much development in the world. The world is full of gadgets and machinery . Machinery does everything in our surroundings. How did it get possible? How did we become so modern? It was all possible with the help of science. Science has played a major role in the development of our society. Furthermore, Science has made our lives easier and carefree.

Essay on science

Science in our Daily Lives

As I have mentioned earlier Science has got many changes in our lives. First of all, transportation is easier now. With the help of Science it now easier to travel long distances . Moreover, the time of traveling is also reduced. Various high-speed vehicles are available these days. These vehicles have totally changed. The phase of our society. Science upgraded steam engines to electric engines. In earlier times people were traveling with cycles. But now everybody travels on motorcycles and cars. This saves time and effort. And this is all possible with the help of Science.

Secondly, Science made us reach to the moon. But we never stopped there. It also gave us a glance at Mars. This is one of the greatest achievements. This was only possible with Science. These days Scientists make many satellites . Because of which we are using high-speed Internet. These satellites revolve around the earth every day and night. Even without making us aware of it. Science is the backbone of our society. Science gave us so much in our present time. Due to this, the teacher in our schools teaches Science from an early age.

Get the huge list of more than 500 Essay Topics and Ideas

Science as a Subject

In class 1 only a student has Science as a subject. This only tells us about the importance of Science. Science taught us about Our Solar System. The Solar System consists of 9 planets and the Sun. Most Noteworthy was that it also tells us about the origin of our planet. Above all, we cannot deny that Science helps us in shaping our future. But not only it tells us about our future, but it also tells us about our past.

When the student reaches class 6, Science gets divided into three more subcategories. These subcategories were Physics, Chemistry, and Biology. First of all, Physics taught us about the machines. Physics is an interesting subject. It is a logical subject.

Furthermore, the second subject was Chemistry . Chemistry is a subject that deals with an element found inside the earth. Even more, it helps in making various products. Products like medicine and cosmetics etc. result in human benefits.

Last but not least, the subject of Biology . Biology is a subject that teaches us about our Human body. It tells us about its various parts. Furthermore, it even teaches the students about cells. Cells are present in human blood. Science is so advanced that it did let us know even that.

Leading Scientists in the field of Science

Finally, many scientists like Thomas Edison , Sir Isaac Newton were born in this world. They have done great Inventions. Thomas Edison invented the light bulb. If he did not invent that we would stay in dark. Because of this Thomas Edison’s name marks in history.

Another famous Scientist was Sir Isaac Newton . Sir Isaac Newton told us about Gravity. With the help of this, we were able to discover many other theories.

In India Scientists A..P.J Abdul was there. He contributed much towards our space research and defense forces. He made many advanced missiles. These Scientists did great work and we will always remember them.

Customize your course in 30 seconds

Which class are you in.

tutor

  • Travelling Essay
  • Picnic Essay
  • Our Country Essay
  • My Parents Essay
  • Essay on Favourite Personality
  • Essay on Memorable Day of My Life
  • Essay on Knowledge is Power
  • Essay on Gurpurab
  • Essay on My Favourite Season
  • Essay on Types of Sports

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Download the App

Google Play

Drishti IAS

  • Classroom Programme
  • Interview Guidance
  • Online Programme
  • Drishti Store
  • My Bookmarks
  • My Progress
  • Change Password
  • From The Editor's Desk
  • How To Use The New Website
  • Help Centre

Achievers Corner

  • Topper's Interview
  • About Civil Services
  • UPSC Prelims Syllabus
  • GS Prelims Strategy
  • Prelims Analysis
  • GS Paper-I (Year Wise)
  • GS Paper-I (Subject Wise)
  • CSAT Strategy
  • Previous Years Papers
  • Practice Quiz
  • Weekly Revision MCQs
  • 60 Steps To Prelims
  • Prelims Refresher Programme 2020

Mains & Interview

  • Mains GS Syllabus
  • Mains GS Strategy
  • Mains Answer Writing Practice
  • Essay Strategy
  • Fodder For Essay
  • Model Essays
  • Drishti Essay Competition
  • Ethics Strategy
  • Ethics Case Studies
  • Ethics Discussion
  • Ethics Previous Years Q&As
  • Papers By Years
  • Papers By Subject
  • Be MAINS Ready
  • Awake Mains Examination 2020
  • Interview Strategy
  • Interview Guidance Programme

Current Affairs

  • Daily News & Editorial
  • Daily CA MCQs
  • Sansad TV Discussions
  • Monthly CA Consolidation
  • Monthly Editorial Consolidation
  • Monthly MCQ Consolidation

Drishti Specials

  • To The Point
  • Important Institutions
  • Learning Through Maps
  • PRS Capsule
  • Summary Of Reports
  • Gist Of Economic Survey

Study Material

  • NCERT Books
  • NIOS Study Material
  • IGNOU Study Material
  • Yojana & Kurukshetra
  • Chhatisgarh
  • Uttar Pradesh
  • Madhya Pradesh

Test Series

  • UPSC Prelims Test Series
  • UPSC Mains Test Series
  • UPPCS Prelims Test Series
  • UPPCS Mains Test Series
  • BPSC Prelims Test Series
  • RAS/RTS Prelims Test Series
  • Daily Editorial Analysis
  • YouTube PDF Downloads
  • Strategy By Toppers
  • Ethics - Definition & Concepts
  • Mastering Mains Answer Writing
  • Places in News
  • UPSC Mock Interview
  • PCS Mock Interview
  • Interview Insights
  • Prelims 2019
  • Product Promos

essay model science

Farming has Lost the Ability to be a Source of Subsistence for...

  • 06 Jun 2024

Reality does not Conform to the Ideal, but Confirms It

  • 31 May 2024

A People that Values Its Privileges Above Its Principles Loses...

  • 23 May 2024

The Past is a Permanent Dimension of Human Consciousness and V...

  • 16 May 2024

Customary Morality cannot be a Guide to Modern Life

  • 10 May 2024

Management of Indian Border Disputes - A Complex Task

  • 02 May 2024

Poverty Anywhere is a Threat to Prosperity Everywhere

  • 24 Apr 2024

A Good Life is One Inspired by Love and Guided by Knowledge

  • 18 Apr 2024

Alternative Technologies for a Climate Change Resilient India

  • 12 Apr 2024

Rise of Artificial Intelligence: The Threat of Jobless Future ...

  • 04 Apr 2024

Biased Media is a Real Threat to Indian Democracy

  • 29 Mar 2024

Neglect of Primary Health Care and Education in India are Reas...

  • 18 Mar 2024

Best for an Individual is not Necessarily Best for The Society

  • 08 Mar 2024

Values Are Not What Humanity Is, But What Humanity Ought To Be

  • 01 Mar 2024

Courage to Accept and Dedication to Improve are Two Keys to Su...

  • 14 Feb 2024

Wisdom Finds Truth

  • 07 Feb 2024

South Asian Societies are Woven not Around The State, but Arou...

  • 30 Jan 2024

Culture is What We are, Civilization is What We Have

  • 24 Jan 2024

Not All who Wander are Lost

  • 18 Jan 2024

Visionary Decision-Making Happens at the Intersection of Intui...

  • 03 Jan 2024

essay model science

Navigation Menu

Search code, repositories, users, issues, pull requests..., provide feedback.

We read every piece of feedback, and take your input very seriously.

Saved searches

Use saved searches to filter your results more quickly.

To see all available qualifiers, see our documentation .

  • Notifications You must be signed in to change notification settings

🐙 Guides, papers, lecture, notebooks and resources for prompt engineering

dair-ai/Prompt-Engineering-Guide

Folders and files.

NameName
1,406 Commits

Repository files navigation

Prompt engineering guide.

Prompt engineering is a relatively new discipline for developing and optimizing prompts to efficiently use language models (LMs) for a wide variety of applications and research topics. Prompt engineering skills help to better understand the capabilities and limitations of large language models (LLMs). Researchers use prompt engineering to improve the capacity of LLMs on a wide range of common and complex tasks such as question answering and arithmetic reasoning. Developers use prompt engineering to design robust and effective prompting techniques that interface with LLMs and other tools.

Motivated by the high interest in developing with LLMs, we have created this new prompt engineering guide that contains all the latest papers, learning guides, lectures, references, and tools related to prompt engineering for LLMs.

🌐 Prompt Engineering Guide (Web Version)

We've partnered with Maven to deliver the following live cohort-based courses on prompt engineering:

LLMs for Everyone (Beginner) - learn about the latest prompt engineering techniques and how to effectively apply them to real-world use cases.

Prompt Engineering for LLMs (Advanced) - learn advanced prompt engineering techniques to build complex use cases and applications with LLMs.

Happy Prompting!

Announcements / Updates

  • 🎓 New course on Prompt Engineering for LLMs announced! Enroll here !
  • 💼 We now offer several services like corporate training, consulting, and talks.
  • 🌐 We now support 13 languages! Welcoming more translations.
  • 👩‍🎓 We crossed 3 million learners in January 2024!
  • 🎉 We have launched a new web version of the guide here
  • 🔥 We reached #1 on Hacker News on 21 Feb 2023
  • 🎉 The Prompt Engineering Lecture went live here

Join our Discord

Follow us on Twitter

Subscribe to our Newsletter

You can also find the most up-to-date guides on our new website https://www.promptingguide.ai/ .

  • Prompt Engineering - LLM Settings
  • Prompt Engineering - Basics of Prompting
  • Prompt Engineering - Prompt Elements
  • Prompt Engineering - General Tips for Designing Prompts
  • Prompt Engineering - Examples of Prompts
  • Prompt Engineering - Zero-Shot Prompting
  • Prompt Engineering - Few-Shot Prompting
  • Prompt Engineering - Chain-of-Thought Prompting
  • Prompt Engineering - Self-Consistency
  • Prompt Engineering - Generate Knowledge Prompting
  • Prompt Engineering - Prompt Chaining
  • Prompt Engineering - Tree of Thoughts (ToT)
  • Prompt Engineering - Retrieval Augmented Generation
  • Prompt Engineering - Automatic Reasoning and Tool-use (ART)
  • Prompt Engineering - Automatic Prompt Engineer
  • Prompt Engineering - Active-Prompt
  • Prompt Engineering - Directional Stimulus Prompting
  • Prompt Engineering - Program-Aided Language Models
  • Prompt Engineering - ReAct Prompting
  • Prompt Engineering - Multimodal CoT Prompting
  • Prompt Engineering - Graph Prompting
  • Prompt Engineering - Function Calling
  • Prompt Engineering - Generating Data
  • Prompt Engineering - Generating Synthetic Dataset for RAG
  • Prompt Engineering - Takling Generated Datasets Diversity
  • Prompt Engineering - Generating Code
  • Prompt Engineering - Graduate Job Classification Case Study
  • Prompt Engineering - Classification
  • Prompt Engineering - Coding
  • Prompt Engineering - Creativity
  • Prompt Engineering - Evaluation
  • Prompt Engineering - Information Extraction
  • Prompt Engineering - Image Generation
  • Prompt Engineering - Mathematics
  • Prompt Engineering - Question Answering
  • Prompt Engineering - Reasoning
  • Prompt Engineering - Text Summarization
  • Prompt Engineering - Truthfulness
  • Prompt Engineering - Adversarial Prompting
  • Prompt Engineering - ChatGPT
  • Prompt Engineering - Code Llama
  • Prompt Engineering - Flan
  • Prompt Engineering - Gemini
  • Prompt Engineering - GPT-4
  • Prompt Engineering - LLaMA
  • Prompt Engineering - Mistral 7B
  • Prompt Engineering - Mixtral
  • Prompt Engineering - OLMo
  • Prompt Engineering - Phi-2
  • Prompt Engineering - Model Collection
  • Prompt Engineering - Factuality
  • Prompt Engineering - Biases
  • Prompt Engineering - Overviews
  • Prompt Engineering - Approaches
  • Prompt Engineering - Applications
  • Prompt Engineering - Collections
  • Prompt Engineering - Tools
  • Prompt Engineering - Notebooks
  • Prompt Engineering - Datasets
  • Prompt Engineering - Additional Readings

We have published a 1 hour lecture that provides a comprehensive overview of prompting techniques, applications, and tools.

  • Video Lecture
  • Notebook with code

Running the guide locally

To run the guide locally, for example to check the correct implementation of a new translation, you will need to:

  • Install Node >=18.0.0
  • Install pnpm if not present in your system. Check here for detailed instructions.
  • Install the dependencies: pnpm i next react react-dom nextra nextra-theme-docs
  • Boot the guide with pnpm dev
  • Browse the guide at http://localhost:3000/

Appearances

Some places where we have been featured:

  • Wall Street Journal - ChatGPT Can Give Great Answers. But Only If You Know How to Ask the Right Question
  • Forbes - Mom, Dad, I Want To Be A Prompt Engineer
  • Markettechpost - Best Free Prompt Engineering Resources (2023)

If you are using the guide for your work or research, please cite us as follows:

MIT License

Feel free to open a PR if you think something is missing here. Always welcome feedback and suggestions. Just open an issue!

Sponsor this project

Contributors 190.

@omarsar

  • Jupyter Notebook 4.4%

Have a language expert improve your writing

Run a free plagiarism check in 10 minutes, generate accurate citations for free.

  • Knowledge Base
  • How to write an expository essay

How to Write an Expository Essay | Structure, Tips & Examples

Published on July 14, 2020 by Jack Caulfield . Revised on July 23, 2023.

“Expository” means “intended to explain or describe something.” An expository essay provides a clear, focused explanation of a particular topic, process, or set of ideas. It doesn’t set out to prove a point, just to give a balanced view of its subject matter.

Expository essays are usually short assignments intended to test your composition skills or your understanding of a subject. They tend to involve less research and original arguments than argumentative essays .

Instantly correct all language mistakes in your text

Upload your document to correct all your mistakes in minutes

upload-your-document-ai-proofreader

Table of contents

When should you write an expository essay, how to approach an expository essay, introducing your essay, writing the body paragraphs, concluding your essay, other interesting articles, frequently asked questions about expository essays.

In school and university, you might have to write expository essays as in-class exercises, exam questions, or coursework assignments.

Sometimes it won’t be directly stated that the assignment is an expository essay, but there are certain keywords that imply expository writing is required. Consider the prompts below.

The word “explain” here is the clue: An essay responding to this prompt should provide an explanation of this historical process—not necessarily an original argument about it.

Sometimes you’ll be asked to define a particular term or concept. This means more than just copying down the dictionary definition; you’ll be expected to explore different ideas surrounding the term, as this prompt emphasizes.

Here's why students love Scribbr's proofreading services

Discover proofreading & editing

An expository essay should take an objective approach: It isn’t about your personal opinions or experiences. Instead, your goal is to provide an informative and balanced explanation of your topic. Avoid using the first or second person (“I” or “you”).

The structure of your expository essay will vary according to the scope of your assignment and the demands of your topic. It’s worthwhile to plan out your structure before you start, using an essay outline .

A common structure for a short expository essay consists of five paragraphs: An introduction, three body paragraphs, and a conclusion.

Like all essays, an expository essay begins with an introduction . This serves to hook the reader’s interest, briefly introduce your topic, and provide a thesis statement summarizing what you’re going to say about it.

Hover over different parts of the example below to see how a typical introduction works.

In many ways, the invention of the printing press marked the end of the Middle Ages. The medieval period in Europe is often remembered as a time of intellectual and political stagnation. Prior to the Renaissance, the average person had very limited access to books and was unlikely to be literate. The invention of the printing press in the 15th century allowed for much less restricted circulation of information in Europe, paving the way for the Reformation.

The body of your essay is where you cover your topic in depth. It often consists of three paragraphs, but may be more for a longer essay. This is where you present the details of the process, idea or topic you’re explaining.

It’s important to make sure each paragraph covers its own clearly defined topic, introduced with a topic sentence . Different topics (all related to the overall subject matter of the essay) should be presented in a logical order, with clear transitions between paragraphs.

Hover over different parts of the example paragraph below to see how a body paragraph is constructed.

The invention of the printing press in 1440 changed this situation dramatically. Johannes Gutenberg, who had worked as a goldsmith, used his knowledge of metals in the design of the press. He made his type from an alloy of lead, tin, and antimony, whose durability allowed for the reliable production of high-quality books. This new technology allowed texts to be reproduced and disseminated on a much larger scale than was previously possible. The Gutenberg Bible appeared in the 1450s, and a large number of printing presses sprang up across the continent in the following decades. Gutenberg’s invention rapidly transformed cultural production in Europe; among other things, it would lead to the Protestant Reformation.

Prevent plagiarism. Run a free check.

The conclusion of an expository essay serves to summarize the topic under discussion. It should not present any new information or evidence, but should instead focus on reinforcing the points made so far. Essentially, your conclusion is there to round off the essay in an engaging way.

Hover over different parts of the example below to see how a conclusion works.

The invention of the printing press was important not only in terms of its immediate cultural and economic effects, but also in terms of its major impact on politics and religion across Europe. In the century following the invention of the printing press, the relatively stationary intellectual atmosphere of the Middle Ages gave way to the social upheavals of the Reformation and the Renaissance. A single technological innovation had contributed to the total reshaping of the continent.

If you want to know more about AI tools , college essays , or fallacies make sure to check out some of our other articles with explanations and examples or go directly to our tools!

  • Ad hominem fallacy
  • Post hoc fallacy
  • Appeal to authority fallacy
  • False cause fallacy
  • Sunk cost fallacy

College essays

  • Choosing Essay Topic
  • Write a College Essay
  • Write a Diversity Essay
  • College Essay Format & Structure
  • Comparing and Contrasting in an Essay

 (AI) Tools

  • Grammar Checker
  • Paraphrasing Tool
  • Text Summarizer
  • AI Detector
  • Plagiarism Checker
  • Citation Generator

An expository essay is a broad form that varies in length according to the scope of the assignment.

Expository essays are often assigned as a writing exercise or as part of an exam, in which case a five-paragraph essay of around 800 words may be appropriate.

You’ll usually be given guidelines regarding length; if you’re not sure, ask.

An expository essay is a common assignment in high-school and university composition classes. It might be assigned as coursework, in class, or as part of an exam.

Sometimes you might not be told explicitly to write an expository essay. Look out for prompts containing keywords like “explain” and “define.” An expository essay is usually the right response to these prompts.

An argumentative essay tends to be a longer essay involving independent research, and aims to make an original argument about a topic. Its thesis statement makes a contentious claim that must be supported in an objective, evidence-based way.

An expository essay also aims to be objective, but it doesn’t have to make an original argument. Rather, it aims to explain something (e.g., a process or idea) in a clear, concise way. Expository essays are often shorter assignments and rely less on research.

Cite this Scribbr article

If you want to cite this source, you can copy and paste the citation or click the “Cite this Scribbr article” button to automatically add the citation to our free Citation Generator.

Caulfield, J. (2023, July 23). How to Write an Expository Essay | Structure, Tips & Examples. Scribbr. Retrieved June 7, 2024, from https://www.scribbr.com/academic-essay/expository-essay/

Is this article helpful?

Jack Caulfield

Jack Caulfield

Other students also liked, academic paragraph structure | step-by-step guide & examples, how to write topic sentences | 4 steps, examples & purpose, how to write an argumentative essay | examples & tips, get unlimited documents corrected.

✔ Free APA citation check included ✔ Unlimited document corrections ✔ Specialized in correcting academic texts

  • Share full article

Advertisement

Supported by

Guest Essay

The Long-Overlooked Molecule That Will Define a Generation of Science

essay model science

By Thomas Cech

Dr. Cech is a biochemist and the author of the forthcoming book “The Catalyst: RNA and the Quest to Unlock Life’s Deepest Secrets,” from which this essay is adapted.

From E=mc² to splitting the atom to the invention of the transistor, the first half of the 20th century was dominated by breakthroughs in physics.

Then, in the early 1950s, biology began to nudge physics out of the scientific spotlight — and when I say “biology,” what I really mean is DNA. The momentous discovery of the DNA double helix in 1953 more or less ushered in a new era in science that culminated in the Human Genome Project, completed in 2003, which decoded all of our DNA into a biological blueprint of humankind.

DNA has received an immense amount of attention. And while the double helix was certainly groundbreaking in its time, the current generation of scientific history will be defined by a different (and, until recently, lesser-known) molecule — one that I believe will play an even bigger role in furthering our understanding of human life: RNA.

You may remember learning about RNA (ribonucleic acid) back in your high school biology class as the messenger that carries information stored in DNA to instruct the formation of proteins. Such messenger RNA, mRNA for short, recently entered the mainstream conversation thanks to the role they played in the Covid-19 vaccines. But RNA is much more than a messenger, as critical as that function may be.

Other types of RNA, called “noncoding” RNAs, are a tiny biological powerhouse that can help to treat and cure deadly diseases, unlock the potential of the human genome and solve one of the most enduring mysteries of science: explaining the origins of all life on our planet.

Though it is a linchpin of every living thing on Earth, RNA was misunderstood and underappreciated for decades — often dismissed as nothing more than a biochemical backup singer, slaving away in obscurity in the shadows of the diva, DNA. I know that firsthand: I was slaving away in obscurity on its behalf.

We are having trouble retrieving the article content.

Please enable JavaScript in your browser settings.

Thank you for your patience while we verify access. If you are in Reader mode please exit and  log into  your Times account, or  subscribe  for all of The Times.

Thank you for your patience while we verify access.

Already a subscriber?  Log in .

Want all of The Times?  Subscribe .

Help | Advanced Search

Computer Science > Machine Learning

Title: transformers are ssms: generalized models and efficient algorithms through structured state space duality.

Abstract: While Transformers have been the main architecture behind deep learning's success in language modeling, state-space models (SSMs) such as Mamba have recently been shown to match or outperform Transformers at small to medium scale. We show that these families of models are actually quite closely related, and develop a rich framework of theoretical connections between SSMs and variants of attention, connected through various decompositions of a well-studied class of structured semiseparable matrices. Our state space duality (SSD) framework allows us to design a new architecture (Mamba-2) whose core layer is an a refinement of Mamba's selective SSM that is 2-8X faster, while continuing to be competitive with Transformers on language modeling.
Comments: ICML 2024
Subjects: Machine Learning (cs.LG)
Cite as: [cs.LG]
  (or [cs.LG] for this version)
  Focus to learn more arXiv-issued DOI via DataCite

Submission history

Access paper:.

  • Other Formats

license icon

References & Citations

  • Google Scholar
  • Semantic Scholar

BibTeX formatted citation

BibSonomy logo

Bibliographic and Citation Tools

Code, data and media associated with this article, recommenders and search tools.

  • Institution

arXivLabs: experimental projects with community collaborators

arXivLabs is a framework that allows collaborators to develop and share new arXiv features directly on our website.

Both individuals and organizations that work with arXivLabs have embraced and accepted our values of openness, community, excellence, and user data privacy. arXiv is committed to these values and only works with partners that adhere to them.

Have an idea for a project that will add value for arXiv's community? Learn more about arXivLabs .

IMAGES

  1. A Guide to Writing Scientific Essays

    essay model science

  2. Writing A Scientific Essay

    essay model science

  3. example model essay

    essay model science

  4. Complete Guide: How to Write a Scientific Essay

    essay model science

  5. Essay On Science In Everyday Life in English

    essay model science

  6. Check Out 8 Science Essay Examples

    essay model science

VIDEO

  1. Best Way to Write Essay On A Science Fair || Essay Writing || Short Essays ||

  2. Science Model

  3. SCIENCE MODELS IDEAS FROM SCIENCE FAIR PART-1

  4. Science project for class 8th students working model easy science exhibition projects class

  5. Science ##/ working model essay

  6. Day and night working model|Easy science project| School Project for Exhibition|Earth rotation model

COMMENTS

  1. Scientific Writing Made Easy: A Step-by-Step Guide to Undergraduate Writing in the Biological Sciences

    This guide was inspired by Joshua Schimel's Writing Science: How to Write Papers that Get Cited and Proposals that Get Funded—an excellent book about scientific writing for graduate students and professional scientists—but designed to address undergraduate students. While the guide was written by a group of ecologists and evolutionary ...

  2. PDF Tutorial Essays for Science Subjects

    Dr Peter Judge | Tutorial Essays for Science Subjects 1 Tutorial Essays for Science Subjects This guide is designed to provide help and advice on scientific writing. Although students studying Medical and Life Sciences are most likely to have to write essays for tutorials at Oxford, it is important all scientists

  3. The Four Main Types of Essay

    Argumentative essays. An argumentative essay presents an extended, evidence-based argument. It requires a strong thesis statement—a clearly defined stance on your topic. Your aim is to convince the reader of your thesis using evidence (such as quotations) and analysis.. Argumentative essays test your ability to research and present your own position on a topic.

  4. 27 Outstanding College Essay Examples From Top Universities 2024

    This college essay tip is by Abigail McFee, Admissions Counselor for Tufts University and Tufts '17 graduate. 2. Write like a journalist. "Don't bury the lede!" The first few sentences must capture the reader's attention, provide a gist of the story, and give a sense of where the essay is heading.

  5. How to Write a Scientific Essay

    Take concise notes while reading, focusing on information relevant to the essay. Identify the most crucial information and examples that support the argument. Begin writing the essay, considering starting with the middle sections for clarity. Circle back to the introduction and conclusion once the main body is outlined.

  6. How to Write a Science Essay

    A science essay is an academic paper focusing on a scientific topic from physics, chemistry, biology, or any other scientific field. ... the traditional classroom model is undergoing a profound transformation. This essay explores the profound impact of technology on modern education, focusing on its ability to enhance learning experiences ...

  7. PDF WRITING A SCIENTIFIC ESSAY

    To introduce an additional idea in addition, another reason/ aspect/example, furthermore, moreover, besides, also To introduce an opposite idea or contrast

  8. Example of a Great Essay

    The structure of an essay is divided into an introduction that presents your topic and thesis statement, a body containing your in-depth analysis and arguments, and a conclusion wrapping up your ideas. The structure of the body is flexible, but you should always spend some time thinking about how you can organize your essay to best serve your ...

  9. How to Write a Scientific Essay

    The most important is that a science essay must be analytical and precise in the delivery of answers. This is because in science essays, there is no room for your opinion or a vague perspective - the aim is to identify objective or impartial logic and accurate knowledge, as well as giving you a forum to demonstrate your judgement and analysis ...

  10. How to Write a Scientific Essay • Oxford Learning College

    Essays need to be written out in continuous prose. You shouldn't be using bullet points or writing in note form. If it helps to make a particular point, however, you can use a diagram providing it is relevant and adequately explained. Look at the topic you are required to write about.

  11. Models in Science

    Models are of central importance in many scientific contexts. The centrality of models such as inflationary models in cosmology, general-circulation models of the global climate, the double-helix model of DNA, evolutionary models in biology, agent-based models in the social sciences, and general-equilibrium models of markets in their respective domains is a case in point (the Other Internet ...

  12. How to Write an Argumentative Essay

    Make a claim. Provide the grounds (evidence) for the claim. Explain the warrant (how the grounds support the claim) Discuss possible rebuttals to the claim, identifying the limits of the argument and showing that you have considered alternative perspectives. The Toulmin model is a common approach in academic essays.

  13. Scientific modelling

    Scientific modelling. In science, a model is a representation of an idea, an object or even a process or a system that is used to describe and explain phenomena that cannot be experienced directly. Models are central to what scientists do, both in their research as well as when communicating their explanations.

  14. Welcome to the Purdue Online Writing Lab

    Mission. The Purdue On-Campus Writing Lab and Purdue Online Writing Lab assist clients in their development as writers—no matter what their skill level—with on-campus consultations, online participation, and community engagement. The Purdue Writing Lab serves the Purdue, West Lafayette, campus and coordinates with local literacy initiatives.

  15. The use of scientific methods and models in the philosophy of science

    Using Web of Science records for all papers written in English and published in the main philosophy of science journals between 2000 and 2020, we first built a bibliographic coupling network based on the cosine similarity between tfidf scores for every pair of research paper matching our search criteria. This network contained \(N=9217\) nodes corresponding to research papers and over one ...

  16. Essay

    FCE Essays - Sample/model answers and examiner comments. An essay is always written for the teacher. It should answer the question given by addressing both content points and providinga new content point of the writer's own. The essay should be well organised, with an introduction and an appropriate conclusion,and should be written in an appropriate register and tone

  17. Exploring the potential of using an AI language model for automated

    The widespread adoption of ChatGPT, an AI language model, has the potential to bring about significant changes to the research, teaching, and learning of foreign languages. The present study aims to leverage this technology to perform automated essay scoring (AES) and evaluate its reliability and accuracy. Specifically, we utilized the GPT-3 ...

  18. Economics : Model Essays (Second Edition)

    Economics: Model Essays is the 2nd edition of the best-selling revision guide that helps students gain a strong grade in the essay component of the 2023-2025 Cambridge International AS & A Level Economics (9708) examination paper. With over 50 new model essays, the book provides a clear essay structure for each essay, various tips, and conceptual diagrams on basic economics concepts to give ...

  19. Essay

    The essay has a neutral tone and uses appropriate phrases to introduce and connect ideas through the text (On theone hand; On the other hand; In my opinion). The essay topic is clearly communicated in the first paragraph and the main points are developed in separate paragraphs.

  20. Essay on Science for Students and Children

    Get the huge list of more than 500 Essay Topics and Ideas. Science as a Subject. In class 1 only a student has Science as a subject. This only tells us about the importance of Science. Science taught us about Our Solar System. The Solar System consists of 9 planets and the Sun. Most Noteworthy was that it also tells us about the origin of our ...

  21. Model Essays

    Reach Us 12, Main AB Road, Bhawar Kuan, Indore, Madhya Pradesh, 452007 641, 1 st Floor, Mukherjee Nagar, Delhi-110009 ; 21, Pusa Rd, WEA, Karol Bagh, Delhi-110005

  22. GitHub

    Prompt engineering is a relatively new discipline for developing and optimizing prompts to efficiently use language models (LMs) for a wide variety of applications and research topics. Prompt engineering skills help to better understand the capabilities and limitations of large language models (LLMs).

  23. Software that detects 'tortured acronyms' in research ...

    In 2022, IOPP retracted nearly 500 papers from conference proceedings after the PPS flagged tortured phrases in the papers. When Eggleton and her team investigated, they found reams of other problems—fake identity, citation cartels in which researchers insert irrelevant references to one another, and even entirely fabricated research.

  24. Seed-TTS: A Family of High-Quality Versatile Speech Generation Models

    We introduce Seed-TTS, a family of large-scale autoregressive text-to-speech (TTS) models capable of generating speech that is virtually indistinguishable from human speech. Seed-TTS serves as a foundation model for speech generation and excels in speech in-context learning, achieving performance in speaker similarity and naturalness that matches ground truth human speech in both objective and ...

  25. How to Write an Expository Essay

    The structure of your expository essay will vary according to the scope of your assignment and the demands of your topic. It's worthwhile to plan out your structure before you start, using an essay outline. A common structure for a short expository essay consists of five paragraphs: An introduction, three body paragraphs, and a conclusion.

  26. It's Not You: Dating Apps Are Getting Worse

    Yet shares (Bumble's stock price has fallen from about $75 to about $11 since its I.P.O.) and user growth have fallen, so the apps have more aggressively rolled out new premium models. In ...

  27. The Long-Overlooked Molecule That Will Define a Generation of Science

    By Thomas Cech. Dr. Cech is a biochemist and the author of the forthcoming book "The Catalyst: RNA and the Quest to Unlock Life's Deepest Secrets," from which this essay is adapted. From E ...

  28. Browse journals and books

    Browse Calls for Papers beta. Browse 5,060 journals and 35,600 books. A; A Review on Diverse Neurological Disorders. Pathophysiology, Molecular Mechanisms, and Therapeutics. Book ... Abridged Science for High School Students. The Nuclear Research Foundation School Certificate Integrated, Volume 1. Book • 1966.

  29. PDF Department of Commerce National Oceanic & Atmospheric Administration

    authored papers may also be submitted, as appropriate to the subject matter, to established "peer review" processes. Papers intended for the peer-reviewed literature (as defined in Attachment 1) undergo internal peer review as outlined in Section 2.a. 2.a. Papers for peer-reviewed literature: The NOAA Framework (item 1c, above) requires that

  30. [2405.21060] Transformers are SSMs: Generalized Models and Efficient

    View PDF Abstract: While Transformers have been the main architecture behind deep learning's success in language modeling, state-space models (SSMs) such as Mamba have recently been shown to match or outperform Transformers at small to medium scale. We show that these families of models are actually quite closely related, and develop a rich framework of theoretical connections between SSMs and ...